Skip to main content

Full text of "The elements of inductive logic: Designed Mainly for the Use of Students in the Universities"

See other formats


Google 



This is a digital copy of a book that was preserved for generations on Hbrary shelves before it was carefully scanned by Google as part of a project 

to make the world's books discoverable online. 

It has survived long enough for the copyright to expire and the book to enter the public domain. A public domain book is one that was never subject 

to copyright or whose legal copyright term has expired. Whether a book is in the public domain may vary country to country. Public domain books 

are our gateways to the past, representing a wealth of history, culture and knowledge that's often difficult to discover. 

Marks, notations and other maiginalia present in the original volume will appear in this file - a reminder of this book's long journey from the 

publisher to a library and finally to you. 

Usage guidelines 

Google is proud to partner with libraries to digitize public domain materials and make them widely accessible. Public domain books belong to the 
public and we are merely their custodians. Nevertheless, this work is expensive, so in order to keep providing this resource, we liave taken steps to 
prevent abuse by commercial parties, including placing technical restrictions on automated querying. 
We also ask that you: 

+ Make non-commercial use of the files We designed Google Book Search for use by individuals, and we request that you use these files for 
personal, non-commercial purposes. 

+ Refrain fivm automated querying Do not send automated queries of any sort to Google's system: If you are conducting research on machine 
translation, optical character recognition or other areas where access to a large amount of text is helpful, please contact us. We encourage the 
use of public domain materials for these purposes and may be able to help. 

+ Maintain attributionTht GoogXt "watermark" you see on each file is essential for informing people about this project and helping them find 
additional materials through Google Book Search. Please do not remove it. 

+ Keep it legal Whatever your use, remember that you are responsible for ensuring that what you are doing is legal. Do not assume that just 
because we believe a book is in the public domain for users in the United States, that the work is also in the public domain for users in other 
countries. Whether a book is still in copyright varies from country to country, and we can't offer guidance on whether any specific use of 
any specific book is allowed. Please do not assume that a book's appearance in Google Book Search means it can be used in any manner 
anywhere in the world. Copyright infringement liabili^ can be quite severe. 

About Google Book Search 

Google's mission is to organize the world's information and to make it universally accessible and useful. Google Book Search helps readers 
discover the world's books while helping authors and publishers reach new audiences. You can search through the full text of this book on the web 

at |http : //books . google . com/| 



^ / 



■f- 

' 1 



L ;. V) / 






^ { » 



/ 



7 



S?.-:*-^ . . 



/.-„ 



) 



Clintn^M l^tm l^mti 



INDUCTIVE LOGIC 



FOWLER 



ZanOon 
MACMILLAN AND CO. 




PUBLISHERS TO THE UNIVERSITY OF 



€lva;tr^an ^r«ss S^nes 



THE ELEMENTS 



OF 



INDUCTIVE LOGIC 



DESIGNED MAINLY 
FOR THE USE OF STUDENTS IN THE UNIVERSITIES 



BY 



THOMAS FOWLER, M.A. 

Fellow and Tutor of Lincoln College, Oxford 




©xforlr 

AT THE CLARENDON PRESS 
MDCCCLXX 

\_All rights reserved'\ 



PREFACE. 



THE object of the following work is to serve as an 
introduction to that branch of scientific method which 
is known as Induction. It is designed mainly for the 
use of those who have not time or opportunity to con- 
sult larger works, or who require some preliminary 
knowledge before they can profitably enter upon the 
study of them. 

To the works of Mr. Mill, Dr. Whewell, and Sir John 
Herschel, the Author must, once for all, express his obH- 
gations. * He has, however,' if he may be allowed to 
repeat the language already employed in the Preface 
to his Manual of Deductive Logic, * endeavoiured, on all 
disputed points, to reason out his own conclusions, feel- 
ing assured that no manual, however elementary, can be 
of real service to the student, imless it express what may 
be called the " reasoned opinions " of its author.' 

The analysis of Induction presents far more difficulties 
than that of Deduction, and requires to be illustrated 



VI PREFACE, 

by far more numerous and more intricate examples. 
But, on the other hand, it is more interesting both to 
the teacher and to the student; and, being a compara- 
tively recent study, is less hampered by conventionalities 
of treatment. Since the time of Bacon, it has always, 
with ""more or less of success, claimed a place in liberal 
education, and many, to whom the technical terms and 
subtle distinctions of the older logic are justly repulsive, 
have experienced a peculiar delight in attempting to 
discover and test the grounds on which the results of 
modem science mainly rest. 

The study of Deductive Logic can be of little service 
unless it be supplemented by, at least, some knowledge 
of the principles of Induction, which supplies its pre- 
misses. Many of the objections directed against the 
study of Logic are due to the narrow conceptions which 
are entertained of its province, and might be easily met 
by showing that the study, when we include both its 
parts, has a much wider range than is popularly assigned 
to it. 

Though the present work is mainly intended for stu- 
dents in the Universities, it is hoped that it will be found 
to present some interest* for the general reader, and that 
it may be useful to students of medicine and the physical 



PREFACE, Vii 

sciences, as well as to some of the more advanced scholars 
in our Public Schools. 

The number of scientific examples adduced throughout 
the work renders it necessary, perhaps, that the Author 
should state emphatically that the work is intended as an 
introduction, not to science, but to scientific method. Its 
object is not to give a r^sum^ of the sciences, physical 
or social, a task to which the Author would be wholly 
incompetent, but to show the grounds on which our 
scientific knowledge rests, the methods by which it has 
been built up, and the defects from which it must be 
free. Notwithstanding its frequent incursions into the 
domain of science, the purport of the work must be 
regarded as strictly logical. 

The examples have, as a rule, been selected from the 
physical rather than the social sciences, as being usually 
less open to dispute, and lying within a smaller compass. 
Wherever it has been possible, they have been given in 
the exact words of the author from whom they are taken. 

Some of the more complicated cases of inductive rea- 
soning, such as those which have to deal with Progres- 
sive Causes or Intermixture of Effects, have, if alluded 
to at all, been only briefly noticed. Any detailed exami- 
nation of these more intricate questions seeovt^ \xi \sr. 



Vlll PREFACE. 

without the scope of the treatise. The student who has 
leisure to pursue the subject will find ample information 
in the pages of Mr. Mill's Logic, 

It only remains for the Author to express his grateful 
acknowledgments to those who have assisted him in the 
execution of the work. These are, in the first place, due 
to Dr. Liddell, Dean of Christ Church, through whose 
hands the sheets have passed, and who, in addition to 
revising the proofs, has, from time to time, offered many 
most valuable suggestions. They are due also, in no 
small degree, to Sir John Herschel and Professor Bar- 
tholomew Price, who most kindly undertook to revise 
the scientific examples; to Professors Rolleston and 
Clifton, who have frequently allowed the Author to con- 
sult them on questions connected with the subjects of 
their respective chairs, and to the Rev. G. W. Kitchin, 
the Organising Secretary of the Clarendon Press Series. 
The Author must, however, be regarded as alone re- 
sponsible for any errors which may occur either in the 
theoretical portion of the work or in the examples. 



Lincoln Collbob, 
Oct, 30, 1869. 



CONTENTS. 



CHAP. PAGE 

I. The Nature of Inductire Inference 3 

II. Processes subsidiary to Induction ...... 33 

§ I . Observation and Experiment . . .33 

•- § 2. Classification, Nomenclature, and Terminology . 45 

(l) Classification 45 

(3) Nomenclature 81 

^ (3) Terminology 84 

§ 3. Hypotbens 89 

III. The Inductive Methods 116 

Method of Agreement lao 

Method of Difference . » 138 

Double Method of Agreement . . . . .150 

Method of Residues 163 

Method of Concomitant Variations . . . • 1 73 

rV. Imperfect Inductions 205 

Inductio per Simplicem Enumerationem . . . 205 

Argument from Analogy 209 

Imperfect applications of the Inductive Methods . .220 



X CONTENTS. 

CHAP. PAGE 

V. The Relation of Induction to Deduction, and Verification . 224 

VI. The Fallacies incident to Induction 237 

A. Fallacies incident to the subsidiary processes . . '237 

I. Fallacy of Non-observation, consisting in neglect either 

(i) of some of the instances . . . •237 
or (2) of some of the circumstances attendant on a 

given instance 250 

n. Fallacy of Mal-observation 254 

m. Errors incidental to the operations of Classification, 

Nomenclature, Terminology, and Hypothesis . 259 

B. Fallacies incident to the Inductive process itself, or Fallacies 

of Generalisation 259 

IV. Error originating in the employment of the Inductio 
per Simplicem Enumerationem (including the illegiti- 
mate use of the Argument from Authority) . .260 
V. Errors common to the emplo3rment of the various In- 
ductive Methods 274 

(i) Mistaking a for the cause of b, when the 

real cause is c 276 

(2) Mistaking a for the sole cause, when a and 

c are the joint causes, either as 
(a) both contributing to the toted effect . 281 
or (jS) being both essential to tiie production of 

any effect whatever .... 285 

(3) Mistaking joint effects for cause and effect . 290 



CONTENTS, XI 

PAGE 

(4) Mistaking the remote cause for the proximate 

cause, or the reverse 294 

(5) Neglecting to take into account the mutual action 

(mutuality) of cause and effect . . . 298 

(6) Inversion of cause and effect . . . • 301 
VI. False analogy (including the illegitimate use of the 

Argument from Antiquity, and of the Argument 
from Final Causes) 304 

Index 331 



^<>:<>;<o>>»:*:>>~ 



'E/c npoyoKoa-KOfiiv&v dc naaa didacrieaXta, Sxnnp kcX iv toIs 
dvoXvrcKoiff Xeyofiev' ^ flip yap di iiraycDy^Sy ff de crvXkoyuTfi^. 
*H fiev drf cTraycoy^ ^PX$ ^*""* ***^ ''O'' iKo^t^Xov, 6 dc avWoyia-fibs 
€K Tap Ka$6Kov, Ela\p &pa ap\cLi i^ hv 6 avXXoyurfihs, ^v ovk 
loTi (rvXXoyi(rfi6s' eiraycoy^ &pa, 

Aristotle's Nicomacbean Etbtcs^ vi. 3 (3). 



Quamvis ad scientiain quamlibet via unica pateat, qua nempe a 
notionibus ad minus nota et a manifestis ad obscuriorum notitiam 
progredimur, atque universalia nobis praecipu^ nota sint (ab univer- 
salibus enim ad particularia ratiocinando oritur scientia), ipsa tamen 
universalium in intellectu comprehensio a singulariuni in sensibus 
nostris perceptione exsurgit. 

Preface to Harvey's Treatise De Generatione Animalium. 



ELEMENTS 



OF 



INDUCTIVE LOGIC. 



B 



*#* The notes appended to the Chapters (as dis- 
tinguished from the foot-notes) are designed to inform 
the student of any divergences from the ordinary mode 
of treatment, or to afford him information on disputed 
questions which it appeared inconvenient to notice in 
the text. They may be omitted on the first reading. 



CHAPTER I. 
On the Nature of Inductive Inference. 

TWO bodies of unequal weight (say a guinea and 
a feather) are placed at the same height under the ex- 
hausted receiver of an air-pump. When released, they 
are observed to reach the bottom of the vessel at the 
same instant of time, or, in other words, to fall in equal 
times. From this fact, it is inferred that a repetition of 
the experiment either with these two bodies or with any 
other bodies would be attended with the same result, and 
that, if it were not for the resistance of the atmosphere 
and other impeding circumstances, all bodies, whatever 
their weight, would fall through equal vertical spaces in 
equal times. Now, that these two bodies in this par- 
ticular experiment fall to the bottom of the receiver in 
equal times is merely a fact of observation, but that they 
would do so if we repeated the experiment, or that the 
next two bodies we selected, or any bodies, or all bodies, 
would do so, is an inference, and is an inference of that 
particular character which is called an Inductive Inference 
or an Induction ^. 

^ The student must throughout bear in mind the ambiguous use of 
the words Induction, Inference, &c., as signifying both the rutdt and 

B a 



4 NATURE OF 

What assumptions underlie this inference, and on what 
grounds does it rest ? 

My object in placing the two bodies under the receiver 
was obviously to answer a question which I had pre- 
viously addressed to myself: viz. whether, when subject 
to the action of gravity^ only, they would fall in equal 
or in unequal times. By exhausting the air in the re- 
ceiver, I am able to tsolafe the phenomenon^ and thus, by 
removing all circumstances affecting the bodies, except 
the action of gravity, to watch the effect of this cause 
operating alone. But in trying this experiment, in iso- 
lating the phenomenon, and asking what will be the effect 
of the action of gravity operating alone, I am evidently 
assuming that the effect, whatever it may be, will be 
entirely due to the cause or causes which are then and 
there in action; in other words, I am assuming that 
nothing can happen without a cause, that no change can 
take place without being preceded or attended by circum- 
stances which, if we were fully acquainted with them, 
would fully account for that change. This assumption 
(which may be called the Law of Universal Causation) 
is universally admitted by mankind, or at least by the 

the process by which the result is arrived at. See Deductive Logic, 
Preface, and Part III. ch. i. note I. 

^ When I employ the expression * action of gravity ' or ' force of 
gravity/ I must not be understood as adopting any particular theory on 
the nature of the phenomenon which we call * gravitation.' I use these 
terms simply because they are short and recognised phrases for expressing 
the fact that all terrestrial bodies, when left entirely free, fall in the 
direction of the earth's centre. 



INDUCTIVE INFERENCE. 5 

reflecting portion of mankind, though the grounds on 
which it is admitted have been variously stated; some 
justifying it by an appeal to the continuous and uncon- 
tradicted experience not only of the individual himself 
but of the human race, others by an appeal to ' the neces- 
sities of thought. 

Thus far, however, we have only ascertained that the 
fact of these two particular bodies, in this particular 
instance, falling to the ground in equal times is due to 
the action of gravity, unimpeded by any other circum- 
stances. But why should I infer that they, if the experi- 
ment were repeated, or any other two bodies, if exposed 
to the same circumstances, would behave in the same 
way ? It is not enough to feel assured that nothing can 
happen without a cause, and that the only cause operating 
in this particular instance is the action of gravity ; I must 
also feel assured that the same cause will ' invariably be 
followed by the same effect, or, to speak more accurately, 
that the same cause or combination of causes, will, if 
unimpeded by the action of any other cause or combina- 
tion of causes, be invariably followed by the same effect 
or combination of effects, or, to state the same proposi- 
tion in somewhat different language, that, whenever the 
same antecedents, and none others, are introduced, the 
same consequents will invariably follow. This assiunp- 

* The expression * will * is used for the sake of convenience. The 
argument, however, is not simply from the present to the future, but 
from cases within the range of our experience to all cases, past, present, 
or future, without that range. See p. a 6, note 19. 



6 NATURE OF 

tion (or law) is, like the former, universally admitted by 
ipankind, or the reflecting portion of mankind, though 
the grounds on which it is admitted have been variously 
stated, some, as in the case of the former law, referring it 
to experience, others to certain necessities of thought 
arising from the original constitution of the human mind. 
This law may be called /he Law of the Uniformity of 
Nature^, 

The argument, then, in the case which we have selected 
as our instance, may be represented as follows : — 

I observe that these two bodies (though of un- 
equal weight) reach the bottom of the receiver 
at the same moment. 
This fact must be due to some cause or com- 
bination of causes (Law of Universal Causation). 
The only cause operating in this instance is the 
action of gravity. 
.-. The fact that these two bodies reach the bottom of 
the receiver at the same moment is due to the 
action of gravity, operating alone. 
But, whenever the same cause or combination of 
causes is in operation, and that only, the same 
eflfect will invariably follow (Law of Uniformity of 
Nature). 

* It is, perhaps, necessary thus early to warn the student that the 
converse of the Law of the Uniformity of Nature does not hold true. 
Though the same cause, that is, the same antecedent or combination of 
antecedents, is never followed by different effects, the same effect may 
be due to different causes. We can, thus, always argue from the cause 
to the effect, but we cannot always argue from the effect to the cause. 



INDUCTIVE INFERENCE, J 

.'. Whenever these two bodies, or any other two or 
more bodies (even though of unequal weight), are 
subject to the action of gravity only, they will 
reach the bottom of the receiver at the same 
moment^ or, in other words, will fall in equal 
times. 
From the above example, and from what has already 
been said in distinguishing Induction from Deduction in 
the Manual of Deductive Logic ^ it will be seen that In- 
duction may be defined as the legitimate inference of the 
unknown from the known, that is, of propositions appli- 
cable to cases hitherto unobserved and unexamined from 
propositions which are known to be true of the cases 
observed and examined. Thus, from the proposition 
that a guinea and a feather, if placed under the exhausted 
receiver of an air-pump, will fall in equal times, may be 
inferred inductively the proposition that a shilling, a 
penny, and a straw will, if exposed to the same circum- 
stances, also fall in equal times. But, as we can only 
draw this inference on grounds which are equally ap- 
plicable to all bodies whatsoever, when exposed to the 
same circumstances, and as we might make the same 
assertion of any two or more bodies, and consequently of 
all bodies, it will be seen that Induction is not only an 
inference of the unknown from the known ; but, in virtue 
of that fact, of the general from the particular. In every 
inductive argument, in fact, it is implied that wherever or 
whenever the same circiunstances are repeated, the same 
effects will follow. Induction may, therefore, also be 



8 NATURE OF 

defined as the legitimate inference of the general from the 
particular y or (in order to include those cases where 
general propositions are themselves employed a3 the 
starting-point of an inductive argument, of which 
nimierous instances will occur as we proceed) of the more 
general from the less general. 

In trying the experiment which has furnished our 
instance in this chapter, we have been attempting to 
find an answer to the question, 'Do bodies, when 
subject to the action of gravity only, fall through 
equal vertical spaces in equal or in unequal times?* 
The experiment may be regarded as an attempt to 
decide between two rival theories (or hypotheses^ as they 
are usually called), one being that bodies fall quicker in 
proportion to their weights, the other that the weight of 
the body, when the resistance of the atmosphere is re- 
moved, makes no difference to the time of falling. The 
experiment is decisive in favour of the latter hypothesis, 
which is thus entitled to rank as a valid induction. Our 
inductions are often, as in this case, the result of an 
attempt to decide between rival hypotheses, or a reply 
to the question whether some particular hypothesis be 
true or not, the hypothesis or hypotheses suggesting the 
particular experiment to be tried. Sometimes, however, 
we have no assistance of this kind, and we try experi- 
ments simply * to see what will come of them.' Thus, 
if a chemist discovers a new element, he will proceed to 
try a variety of experiments in order to determine the 



INDUCTIVE INFERENCE. 9 

proportions in which it will combine with other elements, 
as well as to discover the various properties of such 
combinations. Supposing the experiments to have been 
properly conducted, the inductions at which he arrives 
will be perfectly valid, though he may have formed no 
previous theories as to the results of his researches. Oc- 
casionally, too, an induction will not be the result of any 
definite course of investigation, but will be obtruded on 
our notice, as in the following instance, adduced by Sir 
John Herschel, to show that * after much labour in vain, 
and groping in the dark, accident or casual observation 
will present a case which strikes us at once with a full 
insight into a subject.' * The laws of crystallography 
were obscure, and its causes still more so, till Hauy for- 
tunately dropped a beautiful crystal of calcareous spar 
on a stone pavement, and broke it. In piecing together 
the fragments, he observed their facets not to correspond 
with those of the crystal in its entire state, but to belong 

to another form ; and following out the hint 

thus casually obtruded on his notice, he discovered the 
beautiful laws of the cleavage, and the primitive forms 
of minerals^.' 

Thus, we perceive that our inductions are sometimes 
preceded by hypotheses, at other times not. In most 
cases, probably, we have formed some theory (or hypo- 
thesis) as to the character of a phenomenon before we 
enter upon, or, at least, before we complete, its inves- 
tigation. Such theories (or hypotheses) are often of the 

' Herschel's Discourse on the Study of Natural Philosophy , § 191. 



lO NATURE OF 

Utmost service in directing the course which our experi- 
ments and observations shall take. Frequently, also, it is 
impossible to perform any experiment, or to institute any 
series of observations, which shall be decisive of the 
question before us. In this case, unless we altogether 
suspend our judgment, we must rest content with an 
unproved theory, and it becomes of prime importance to 
determine to what conditions such a theory (or hypo- 
thesis) must conform in order to entitle it to rank as a 
probable or possible solution of our difficulties. A sub- 
sequent section will be specially devoted to these ques- 
tions, but meanwhile it seemed desirable at once to direct 
the attention of the student to the distinction between 
hypothesis and induction. He must bear in mind that, 
though the formation of hypotheses is frequently an im- 
portant step in the inductive process, a hypothesis must 
be carefully distinguished from a valid induction. With- 
out at present attempting any formal definition of a 
hypothesis, it may be distinguished from an induction 
(that is, a valid, complete, or perfect induction) as a mere 
supposition or assumption from an ascertained truth. 

*4.* The word 'cause' is commonly used in a very 
vague and indefinite sense. Of the various antecedents 
whose presence or absence is essential to the event, 
it is usual to single out one as the Cause, and either to 
overlook the others, or to speak of them as * conditions.' 
Strictly speaking, however, the Cause consists in the pre- 
sence of all those antecedents, the withdrawal of any of 



INDUCTIVE INFERENCE. II 

which, and in the absence of all those antecedents, the 
introduction of any of which, might frustrate the event. 
Thus, to take the homely instance of lighting a fire. The 
application of the lighted match is what would ordinarily 
be called the cause of the combustion. But there are 
other conditions equally necessary, as, for instance, 
amongst the positive conditions, the presence of fuel and 
of atmospheric air, and, amongst the negative conditions, 
the absence of such a quantity of moisture as would pre- 
vent the fuel from igniting. In assigning the cause of a 
phenomenon, it is seldom that the negative conditions are 
mentioned. It is generally imderstood that we assign a 
cause, subject to the qualification *no counteracting 
cause intervening.' Amongst the positive conditions, we 
usually select that which, being last introduced, completes 
the assemblage of conditions, and stands in closest prox- 
imity to the effect. Thus, in our example, the combus- 
tion is said to be due to the application of the match, 
and, when a man, who has previously been in a bad state 
of health, is attacked by a fever, we speak of the fever as 
the cause of his death. These, however, as observed by 
Mr. Mill, are by no means invariable rules. * It must not 
be supposed that in the emplojnnent of the term this or 
any other rule is always adhered to. Nothing can better 
show the absence of any scientific ground for the dis- 
tinction between the cause of a phenomenon and its con- 
ditions, than the capricious manner in which we select 
from among the conditions that which we choose to 
denominate the cause. However numerous the con- 



12 NATURE OF 

ditions may be, there is hardly any of them which may 
not, according to the pmpose of our immediate dis- 
com'se, obtain that nominal pre-eminence/ Thus, if 
a plot of dry heath is ignited by a spark from a railway- 
engine, we may, in conmion parlance, attribute the fire 
either to the spark, or to the dryness of the heath, or to the 
ill construction of the engine ; the first of these assigned 
causes being the proximate event, the second one of the 
other positive conditions, the last a negative condition. 
What, when employing popular language, we dignify 
with the name of Cause is that condition which happens 
to be most prominent in our minds at the time. It is, 
perhaps, superfluous to add that, when aiming at scien- 
tific accuracy, we ought to enumerate all the conditions, 
or, at least, all the positive conditions, on which a phe- 
nomenon depends, unless we have a right to presume 
that there is no likelihood of their being overlooked by 
those whom we address ®. 

In the science of Medicine, the cause which completes 
the assemblage of conditions is often distinguished as the 
exciting cause, the other causes being cdHHtdipre-disposing, 
Thus, the peculiarities of constitution, age, sex, occupa- 
tion, &c., which render a person more than ordinarily 
liable to any particular disorder, would be called the pre- 
disposing causes; the contagion (by which the body is 
brought into ^contact with some specific poison), a sud- 
den chill, bodily fatigue, mental depression, or any cir- 

' The subject of this paragraph is treated with great ability in Mr. 
MiU's Logic, Bk. III. ch. v. § 3. 



INDUCTIVE INFERENCE. 13 

cumstance, on the supervention of which the disease is 
immediately consequent, would be called the exciting 
cause''. The pre-disposing causes of Asiatic Cholera, 
for instance, are enumerated in Dr. Guy's Edition of Dr. 
Hooper's * Vade Mecum,' as * debility ; impaired health ; 
intemperance ; impure air ; low and damp situations ; the 
summer and autumn seasons : the exciting causes as con- 
tagion; a peculiar poison diffused through the atmosphere.' 
The importance of attending to this distinction in histori- 
cal and political investigations is forcibly stated and illus- 
trated by Sir G. C. Lewis, in his Methods of Observation 
and Reasoning in Politics, vol. i. ch. ix. p. 333, &c. 



Note I ^. — Mr. Mill {Logic, vol. ii. ch. iii.) maintains 
that all inference (by which he means inductive inference) 
is from particulars to particulars. Dr. Whewell, on the 
other hand, holds that all inductive inference is from the 
particular to the general. {Philosophy of Discovery, 
ch. xxii. § 1-14.) Though I prefer Dr. Whewell's mode 
of statement (which is that ordinarily employed) and have 
adopted it in the text, I cannot recognise the importance 
of the difference which he believes to exist between 
himself and Mr. Mill. To say that what I find to be 
true of this case will be true of the next which resembles 

' See Dr. Watson's Lectures on Pbysic, Lecture VI. 

^ The student, unless he have some previous acquaintance with the 
subjects discussed in them, is recommended to omit these notes on the 
first reading. 



14 NATURE OF 

it in certain assignable respects, \diatever that case may 
be, or that what I found to be true of that case must 
be true of this (the instance being taken indifFerently), 
because this resembles that in certain assignable respects, 
is virtually to say that it is true of any and every case 
which presents these points of resemblance. What is 
true of any case, taken indifferently, must be true • of all, 
* The burnt child dreads the fire/ Why ? because it once 
suffered pain, from burning its finger. Now, it appears 
to me indifferent whether we represent the child as 
having in its mind the proposition ' That object causes 
pain,' or the proposition * That object will cause me pain 
now, if I approach too near to it.' But, as the former 
(the general) inference seems to be undoubtedly implied 
in the latter (the particular), I prefer adhering to the 
common, and, as I think, the more intelligible account of 
induction. Mr. Mill is hardly consistent in his language. 
He himself, in one place, speaks of Induction as * generali- 
sation from experience,' and, in another, as ' the inference 
of a more general from less general propositions.' 

Though agreeing with Dr. Whewell in his main 
position, I must express my entire dissent from the 
distinction which, throughout this discussion, he attempts 
to draw between our reasonings in the ordinary affairs 
of life, and Induction as employed in scientific research. 
However various may be the conditions of their applica- 
tion, I cannot but regard the mental processes as iden- 
tical, on whatever classes of objects they may be exercised. 
We may meet with insurmountable difficulties in the 



INDUCTIVE INFERENCE. 1 5 

attempt to apply Induction to some obscure question 
of Physiology, and we may employ it with ease and 
success a hundred times a day in avoiding pain or se- 
curing ease, but I believe the mental process to be 
essentially the same in both cases. 

JVo/e 2L — Since the time of Hume, the nature of our 
conception of Cause has formed one of the principal 
topics of philosophical controversy. Previously to his 
time, it appears to have been taken for granted by the 
great majority of modem philosophers of all schools* (if 
we except those who, like Malebranche, believed God 
to be the only efficient cause in the universe, and so- 
called acts of causation to be only the occasions of the 
Divine interference^^), that the idea of causation neces- 
sarily implies the idea of power or necessary connection ; 
necessary connection^ that is to say, between the cause and 
efiect, or power in the cause to produce the effect. Even 
Locke, who effected a revolution in modem philosophy, 
left this idea of Power unassailed, though he attempted 
to account for its formation. 'The mind,' says he^^, 

• Dugald Stewart (in his Pbilosopby of the Human Mindj Notes 
G and MM) has certainly succeeded in showing that Hume's views on 
the nature of Cause were anticipated by casual remarks of several other 
writers ; but it still remains true that Hirnie was the first philosopher 
who definitely attacked the prevalent philosophical theory. 

^® Still, even according to these philosophers, every act of causation 
implied an act of power, only that the power was exerted not by the 
so-called cause, but by the Deity himself. It will be noticed that I 
speak only of modem philosophers. Into the difficult question of the 
notions of causation entertained by ancient writers I do not enter. 

^ Locke's Essay t vol. ii. ch. xxi. § i. 



1 6 NATURE OF 

' being every day informed, by the senses, of the 
alteration of those simple ideas it observes in things 
without; and taking notice how one comes to an end, 
and ceases to be, and another begins to exist, which 
was not before; reflecting also on what passes within 
itself, and observing a constant change of its ideas, 
sometimes by the impression of outward objects on the 
senses, and sometimes by the determination of its own 
choice; and concluding from what it has so constantly 
observed to have been, that the like changes will for the 
future be made, in the same things, by like agents, and 
by the like ways, considers in one thing the possibility of 
having any of its simple ideas changed, and in another 
the possibility of making that change ; and so comes by 
that idea which we call Power. Thus we say, fire has 
a power to melt gold, i.e. to destroy the consistency of 
its insensible parts, and consequently its hardness, and 
make it fluid ; and gold has a power to be melted : that 
the sun has a power to blanch wax, and wax a power to 
be blanched by the sun, whereby the yellowness is de- 
stroyed, and whiteness made to exist in its room. In 
which, and the like cases, the power we consider, is in 
reference to the change of perceivable ideas. For we 
cannot observe any alteration to be made in, or operation 
upon anything, but by the observable change of its 
sensible ideas ; nor conceive any alteration to be made, 
but by conceiving a change of some of its ideas.' He 
then proceeds to include our idea of Power amongst 
our Simple Ideas. Hume contested the validity of this 



INDUCTIVE INFERENCE. 17 

idea by an appeal to experience. Whence do we obtain 
this notion of necessary connection between two events ? 
Do we observe any such connection in the events which 
take place in the external world, or in the relation between 
volition and the motion of the organs of the body, or in 
the act of the will by which it summons up, dwells on, 
or dismisses ideas ? ' We have sought in vain for an 
idea of power or necessary connection, in all the soiuces 
from which we could suppose it to be derived. It ap- 
pears, that, in single instances of the operation of bodies, 
we never can, by our utmost scrutiny, discover anything but 
one event following another ; without being able to com- 
prehend any force or power, by which the cause operates, 
or any connection between it and its supposed effect. 
The same difficulty occurs in contemplating the opera- 
tions of mind on body ; where we observe the motion of 
the latter to follow upon t!ie volition of the former ; but 
are not able to observe or conceive the tie, which binds 
together the motion and volition, or the energy by which 
the mind produces this effect. The authority of the will 
over its own faculties and ideas is not a whit more com- 
prehensible : so that, upon the whole, there appears not, 
throughout all nature, any one instance of connection, 
which is conceivable by us. All events seem entirely 
loose and separate. One event follows another ; but we 
never can observe any tie between them. They seem 
conjoined, but never connected. And as we can have no 
idea of anything, which never appeared to our outward 
sense or inward sentiment, the necessary conclusion seems 





l8 NATURE OF 

to be, that we have no idea of connection or power at all, 
and that these words are absolutely without any meaning, 
when employed either in philosophical reasonings, or 
common life^^/ Does Hume then deny th^/acf of causa- 
tion] namely, that, when we have been accustomed to 
observe one event invariably followed by another, we may 
confidently expect, other circumstances remaining the 
same, that it will continue to be followed by it in the 
future, and that, if we perceive a change in any phe- 
nomenon, we may be confident that some other event has 
preceded that change? Certainly not. There is, in 
Hume's writings, absolutely no foundation for the viru- 
lence with which he is attacked by Reid*'. What he 

^* Hume's Essays, Essay on the Idea of Necessary Causation. 

*^ The following may serve as a specimen of Reid's diatribes against 
Hume. * Of all the paradoxes this author has advanced, there is not 
one more shocking to the human undtestanding than this, That things 
may begin to exist without a cause. This would put an end to all 
speculation, as well as to all the business of life. The employment 
of speculative men, since the beginning of the world, has been to 
investigate the causes of things. What pity is it, they never thought 
of putting the previous question, Whether things have a cause or not ? 
This question has at last been started ; and what is there so ridiculous 
as not to be maintained by some philosopher?' — Active Powers^ Essay I. 
ch. iv. Sir W. Hamilton and Dr. Mansel take a far juster view of Hume's 
position. Even Sir W. Hamilton, however, in commenting on Reid's 
statement, says, * This * (namely. That things may begin to exist without 
a cause) * is not Hume's assertion ; but that, on the psychological doc- 
trine generally admitted, we have no valid assurance that they may not.* 
The latter is, certainly, not Hume's assertion. It is true that he bases 
the notion of causation on experience, but then he regards experience 
as the sole source of all our knowledge. Sir William Hamilton's note 
requires only to be compared with the following passage from the 



INDUCTIVE INFERENCE. 19 

called in question was not the invariableness of the fact 
of causation, but the grounds of the prevalent notions 
attached to the word Cause. Whether his speculations 
on this subject be well or ill-founded, he certainly did 
not deny the correctness of the principles on which men 
act in ordinary life or which guide them in scientific 
research. 

There is another objection to the statements contained 
in Hume's Essay which is better founded than the fore- 
jB^oing. If the term ' cause ' be .convertible with the term 
* invariable antecedent,' it has been justly objected by 
Reid^* that we might speak of day as the cause of night, 
and of night as the cause of day. That there are loose 
expressions in the Essay, in which the cause seems to 
be confounded with the invariable antecedent or the 
sum of the invariable antecedents, cannot be denied. 
Such is the following : * Suitably to this experience, 
therefore, we may define a cause to be an object, 
followed by another, and when all the objects, similar 
to the first, are followed by objects similar to the second.' 
But then the sentence proceeds : ' Or, in other words, 
where y if the first object had not heen^ the second never had 
existed^ Now this alternative definition is not open to 
Reid's objection, and a simpler and less questionable 

Essay : * But when one particular species of event has always, in all 
instances, been conjo ned with another, we make no longer any scruple 
of foretelling one upon the appearance of the other, and of employing 
that reasoning, which can alone assure us of any matter of fact or 
existence.' 
" Active Powers^ Essay IV. ch. iii. 

C 2 



20 NATURE OF 

definition of cause has probably never been proposed. 
Slightly modified, it would run thus : ' Cause and Effect 
are two events, or sets of events, which are so related, 
that, if the first had not been, the second had never existed/ 
The first author of eminence who adopted Hume's 
view of the nature of Cause was Dr. Thomas Brown ; 
singularly enough, however, so far from assuming with 
Hume that its origin was to be found in experience, he 
regarded it as instinctive. The notion of 'Power' he 
supposed was simply a gratuitous hypothesis, needlessly 
interpolated between the antecedent, which we call the 
Cause, and the consequent, which we call the Effect. 
* We are eager to supply, by a littie guess-work of 
fancy, the parts unobserved, and suppose deficiencies 
in our observation where there may truly have been 
none ; till at length, by this habitual process, every 
phenomenon becomes, to our imagination, the sign of 
something intermediate as its cause, the discovery of 
which is to be an explanation of the phenomenon. The 
mere succession of one event to another appears, to us, 
very difiicult to be conceived, because it wants that inter- 
vening something, which we have learned to consider as 
a cause : but there seems to be no longer any mystery, 
if we can only suppose something intervening between 
them, and can thus succeed in doubling the diflficulty, 
which we flatter ourselves with having removed; since, 
by the insertion of another link, we must now have two 
sequences of events instead of one simple sequence^*.' 

^^ Brown's Lectures on the Pbilosopby of the Human Mind, Lecture 
IX. Cf. Lecture IL 



INDUCTIVE INFERENCE. 21 

Hume's position is also accepted by James Mill in his 
Analysts of the Phenomena of the Human Mind, and by 
John Stuart Mill in his System of Logic. 

Hume's antagonists have generally (with Kant) com- 
bated his arguments by denying the assumption on which 
they are based, namely, that the origin of our conception 
of Cause is to be sought in experience. Hume, it will be 
recollected, challenges those who maintain the hypothesis 
of * power ' or * necessary connection ' to show how we 
can have become acquainted with it. Does it come from 
our experience of the external world, or from our experi- 
ence of the control of our will over our own acts or our own 
thoughts ? The answer of the Kantian School would be 
that it does not come from experience at all, that it is one 
of those fundamental conceptions which are native to the 
human mind, not given by experience but evoked by it. 
Others, like Reid and Stewart, to whom we may add 
M. Maine de Biran, surrender the notion of power as 
applied to causation in the external world, while they 
maintain it as applied to our own actions, which are the 
results of will. We are conscious, they say, of power in 
ourselves, though we perceive only succession in the ex- 
ternal world. Dr. Mansel, following Cousin, adopts a 
third view, and maintains that the notion of ' Power ' is 
given only in the control of the mind over its own opera- 
tions. ' The intuition of Power is not immediately given 
in the action of matter upon matter ; nor yet can it be 
g^ven in the action of matter upon mind, nor in that of 
mind upon matter ; for to this day we are utterly ignorant 



Z2 NATURE OF 

how matter and mind operate upon each other. We 
know not how the material refractions of the eye are 
connected with the mental sensation of seeing, nor how 
the determination of the will operates in bringing about 
the motion of the muscles. We can investigate severally 
the phenomena of matter and of mind, as we can examine 
severally the constitution of the earth, and the architecture 
of the heavens : we seek the boundary line of their junc- 
tion, as the child chases the horizon, only to discover that 
it flies as we pursue it. There is thus no alternative, but 
either to abandon the inquiry after an immediate intuition 
of power, or to seek for it in mind as determining its awn 
modifications ; — a course open to those who admit ah 
immediate consciousness of self, and to them only. My 
first and only presentation of power or causality is thus to 
be found in my consciousness of myself as willing ^^' 

The relation subsisting between an act of will and the 
motion of the limbs, or between a physical antecedent and 
its consequent, he regards as beyond our knowledge. 
*Our clearest notion of efl&ciency is that of a relation 
between two objects, similar to that which exists between 
ourselves and our volitions. But what relation can exist 
between the heat of fire and the melting of wax, similar 
to that between a conscious mind and its self-determina- 
tions ? Or, if there is nothing precisely similar, can there 
be anything in any degree analogous? We cannot say 
that there is, or, if there is, how far the analogy extends, 
and how and where it fails. We can form no positive 

" Prolegomena Logica, pp. 138, 139. 



INDUCTIVE INFERENCE, 2^ 

conception of a power of thistkind : we can only say, that 
it is something different from the only power of which we 
are intuitively conscious. But, on the other hand, we are 
not warranted in denying the existence of anything of 
the kind ; for denial is as much an act of positive thought 
as affirmation, and a negative idea furnishes no data for 
one or the other ^^.' 

It would, however, be beside my purpose to enter into 
a detailed account of the history of this controversy. 
On account, however, of its historical importance, it 
seemed essential to notice it, and to point out that, what- 
ever theory may be adopted as to the nature of Cause, 
and however great our inability to conceive how one 
event is followed by another, there is, at least, sufficient 
definiteness in the conception to entitle it to be accepted 
as the basis of scientific reasoning. Whether we acknow- 
ledge that one event has invariably the power of producing 
another, or whether we content ourselves with asserting 
that it is invariably followed by that other, it is, in either 
case, the element of invartableness which makes the 
connection or conjunction, whichever we may call it, a 
fitting object of scientific research. But remove the 
element of invariableness, and suppose, if it be sup- 
posable, that the same antecedent or set of antecedents 
is sometimes followed by one consequent, and sometimes 
by another, and sometimes by none at all ; in that case 
science would be impossible. 

The student who wishes to obtain further information 

" Prolegomena Logica^ p. 140. 



24 NATURE OF 

on this controversy (a controversy, however, which pos- 
sesses a historical rather than a practical or scientific 
interest), is referred to Hume's Essay on the Idea of 
Necessary Connection; Dugald Stewart's Dissertation, Part 
II. sect. 8; Mill's Logic, Book III. ch. v; Sir W. HamU- 
ton's Lectures on Metaphysics, Lectures XXXIX, XL; 
Hansel's Prolegomena Logica, ch. v; Mill on Hamilton, 
ch. xvi ; Lewes' History of Philosophy, Articles on Hume 
and Kant. I refer only to books likely to be within the 
student's reach. In quoting or referring to Hume, I 
have employed only his Essays, Many writers persist in 
making references to his Treatise of Human Nature, a 
work which he himself repudiated, as containing an im- 
mature expression of his opinions. In the Advertisement 
to his Essays, he desires that ' the following Pieces may 
alone be regarded as containing the author's philosophical 
sentiments and principles.' 

Note 3. — That a cause is ; that every 

event has a cause; that the same cause is always at- 
tended with the same effect ; are obviously three distinct 
propositions, and still there are few writers who, in their 
treatment of the question of Causation, have not more 
or less confounded them. The first proposition (if 
completed) would be the Definition of Cause, the pre- 
dicate, of course, depending on the view adopted with 
reference to the question discussed in the previous note. 
The second is a statement of the Law of Universal Causa- 
tion, the third of the Law of the Uniformity of Nature. 

It will be observed that in the text of this chapter I 



INDUCTIVE INFERENCE. 25 

have said of each of these laws that it 'is universally 
admitted by mankind, or, at least, by the reflecting portion 
of mankind/ The latter clause must be regarded as 
emphatic, and suggests, I think, a sufficient answer 
to those authors who call in question their universal 
reception. Mr. Lewes, speaking of the Law of Universal 
Causation, says, * All believe irresistibly in particular acts 
of causation. Few believe in universal causation; and 
those few not till after considerable reflections^.' He then 
proceeds to adduce the case of a student of chemistry, 
who could not be convinced of the truth of the Law, 
but 'looked upon the argument as an unwarrantable 
assumption/ Now I venture to think that this incapacity 
was due to the terms of the proposition not being made 
sufficiently intelligible to him. I question whether any 
man of average powers of understanding could be found 
who would maintain the contradictory of either of these 
Laws; who would assert, that is to say, that an event 
might happen without anything to account for it, or that 
a repetition of exactly the same circumstances might be 
followed by a different effect. That a considerable 
amount of intelligence is necessary in ordef to understand 
the general terms in which the propositions are stated, 
is undeniable, but, when once understood, I presume that 
the propositions cannot fail to be acquiesced in. Like 
all other propositions, however, of wide import, they 
may be both understood and acquiesced in, without being 
fully realized. It is the full and constant realization of 

" Lewes' History of Philosophy t Article on Kant. 



26 NATURE OF 

these Laws, at all times and under all circumstances, 
which mainly distinguishes the man of scientific from the 
man of unscientific habits of thought. The unscientific 
man either does not think of inquiring into the causes 
of the phenomena around him, or notes with little pre- 
cision the circumstances which he is investigating. The 
scientific man, on the other hand, insists on invariably 
referring the phenomena in which he is interested to 
their several causes, and is satisfied with nothing but the 
most rigorous inquiry into the relation between these 
causes and their effects. 

But, it may be asked, if the Laws of Universal Causa- 
tion and of the Uniformity of Nature are, on reflection, 
thus universally received, by what mental process do 
men assure themselves of their truth ? Of the origin of 
these, as of kindred beliefs, two different explanations 
are offered by rival schools of psychologists. According 
to one school, the human mind is so constituted that it 
cannot but accept them; they are fundamental beliefs 
which exist in the mind prior to all experience, though 
it is experience which occasions, us to realise our pos- 
session of them. We have never learnt them ; we have 
simply discovered that we possess them. Thus Reid, 
speaking of our conviction that the future will resemble 
the past^® (what we have called the Law of the Uniformity 

" This, however, is a very inadequate statement of the Law of the Uni- 
formity of Nature. * It has been well pointed out,* says Mr. Mill, * that 
Time, in its modifications of past, present, and future, has no concern either 
with the belief itself, or with the grounds of it. We believe that fire will 



INDUCTIVE INFERENCE. %*] 

of Nature), says, 'The wise Author of our nature hath 
implanted in human minds an original principle by which 
we believe and expect the continuance of the course of 
nature, and the continuance of those connections which 
we have observed in times past. It is by this general 
principle of our nature, that, when two things have been 
found connected in time past, the appearance of the one 
produces the belief of the other *^.' And Dr. Whewell, 
speaking of the Law of Universal Causation, says, ' We 
assert that "Every event must have a cause:" and this 
proposition we know to be true, not only probably, and 
generally, and as far as we can see : but we cannot 
suppose it to be false in any single instance. We are 
as certain of it as of the truths of arithmetic or geometry. 
We cannot doubt that it must apply to all events past 
and future, in every part of the universe, just as truly 
as to those occurrences which we have ourselves observed. 
What causes produce what effects ; — ^what is the cause 
of any particular event ; — what will be the effect of any 
peculiar process ; — these are points on which experience 

burn to-morrow, because it burned to day and yesterday ; but we believe, 
on precisely the same grounds, that it burned before we were bom, and 
that it burns this very day in Cochin-China. It is not from the past to 
the future, as past and future, that we infer, but from the known to the 
unknown ; from facts observed to facts unobserved ; from what we have 
perceived, or been directly conscious of, to what has not come within our 
experience. In this last predicament is the whole region of the future ; 
but also the vastly greater portion of the present and of the past* — 
Mill's Logic^ Bk. III. ch. iii. 

^ Reid's Inquiry into the Humttn Mind on the Principles of Common 
Sense, chap. vi. sect. 24. 



7,S NATURE OF 

may enlighten us. Observation and experience may be 
requisite, to enable us to judge respecting such matters. 
But that every event has some cause, Experience cannot 
prove any more than she can disprove. She can add 
nothing to the evidence of the truth, however often she 
may exemplify it. This doctrine, then, cannot have been 
acquired by her teaching ^^.' 

The opposite school of psychologists (of which Mr. 
Mill and Mr. Alexander Bain may be taken as the modern 
representatives) maintains that there is nothing in these 
and kindred beliefs which compels us to distinguish them 
generically from other truths, but that, like all other truths, 
they are the results of Experience. From our earliest 
years, we have been so constantly accustomed to observe 
one change preceded by another change, and the same 
antecedents followed by the same consequents, as well as 
to find our own experience in these respects corroborated 
by that of others, that, on reflection, we all acquiesce, and 
cannot but acquiesce, in the statements which generalize 
these facts. This, it is held, is a sufficient explanation of 
that universality and necessity, which, by the advocates of 
the intuitional theory, described in the last paragraph, are 
supposed to discriminate the ' fundamental beliefs of the 
human mind' or *the principles of common sense,' as 
they are called by these authors, from all other truths. 
The beliefs have acquired the character of universality 
and necessity, not because they have sprung from any 
other source than our ordinary beliefs, but because of the 

^ Whewell's History of Scientific Ideas, Bk. III. ch. ii. § i. 



INDUCTIVE INFERENCE. 29 

constancy and variety of the experience from which they 
are gained. * In fact, our whole lives/ says James Mill, 
* are but a series of changes, that is, of antecedents and 
consequents. The conjunction, therefore, is incessant; 
and, of course, the union of the ideas perfectly insepa- 
rable. We can no more have the idea of an event with- 
out having the ideas of its antecedents and its conse- 
quents, than we can have the idea and not have it at the 
same time ^,* But here . occurs a difficulty. If the Laws 
of Universal Causation and of the Uniformity of Nature 
are inferred from particular facts of causation, are gene- 
ralisations from experience, or, in other words, inductions, 
how is it that they are made the grounds of all other 
inductions? Is not this to argue in a circle? The 
answer to this difficulty is that the Laws in question are 
the result of* an imiform and constant experience, co- 
extensive not with the life of the single individual who 
employs them, but with the entire history of the human 
race; that, consequently, when we adduce them as the 
grounds on which our other inductions rest, we are per- 
forming the perfectly legitimate process of resolving 
narrower into wider cases of experience. The argument, 
in short, is this: the inference from this narrow field of 
observation (the particular induction which we happen to 

^ James 'M\\V% Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind^ ch. xi. 
The position maintained by James Mill is that these beliefs owe their 
universality to the fact of their being inseparably associated with all our 
other cognitions. This is only another mode of stating the theory which 
derives them from experience. 



3© NATURE OF 

be making) must be allowed to be trae, unless we are 
prepared to deny one or other of the much wider gene- 
ralisations which constitute the Laws of Universal Causa- 
tion and of the Uniformity of Nature. To recur to the 
instance adopted in the text, the proposition that bodies, 
subject to the action of gravity only, fall in equal times, 
can be called in question only on peril of doubting one 
or other of the laws ; thus, the doubt which might attach 
to it is shifted to two other propositions which no one 
would think of questioning. Or, to state the same posi- 
tion in a slightly different form, this particular instance is 
shown to be a member of an infinitely long series, the 
other members of which have been examined and ap- 
proved; as, therefore, it differs in no essential respect 
from them, it claims to be admitted also. There is, in- 
deed, throughout this argument one assumption ; as the 
rival theory assumed the trustworthiness of what it styled 
our * fundamental beliefs,' so this assumes the validity of 
experience. But, unless we make one or other of these 
assumptions, we must be prepared to maintain that know- 
ledge is altogether impossible ^^. 

There is a third theory of the origin of universal beliefs 

^ It should be noticed that Dr. Mansel, while agreeing in the main, as 
he usually does, with the intuitional school in respect to the origin of 
our belief in the Law of Universal Causation, refers to experience the 
origin of our belief in the Uniformity of Nature. * The belief in the 
uniformity of nature is not a necessary truth, however constantly guar- 
anteed by our actual experience.* Mansel's Metaphysics^ Chapter on 
Necessary Truths. Cf. Prolegomena Logical ch. v. Dr. Mansel's treat- 
ment of these questions is, in many respects, peculiar to himself. 



INDUCTIVE INFERENCE. 3 1 

which combines, with certain modii&cations, both the 
others. It would admit that all beliefs alike are ultimately 
derived from experience, and still it would freely adopt 
the language that there are some beliefs which are * native 
to the human mind/ The word 'experience,' as or- 
dinarily employed by psychologists, includes not only the 
experience of the individual, but the recorded experience 
of mankind. On the theory, however, of which we are 
now speaking, it has a still more extended meaning ; it 
includes experience, or, to speak more strictly, a peculiar 
facility for forming certain experiences, transmitted by 
hereditary descent from generation to generation. While 
some ideas occur only to particular individuals, at par- 
ticular times, there are others which, from the frequency 
and constancy with which they are obtruded upon men's 
minds at all times and under all circumstances, become, 
after an accumulated experience of many generations, 
connatural, as it were, to the human mind. We assume 
them, often unconsciously, in our special perceptions, and 
when the propositions, which embody them, are pro- 
pounded to us, we find it impossible, on reflection, to 
doubt their truth. It is by personal experience of ex- 
ternal objects and their relations that each man recognises 
them, but the tendency to recognise them is transmitted, 
like the physical or mental peculiarities of race, from 
preceding generations, and is anterior to any special ex- 
perience whatever on the part of the individual. This 
theory, to which much of modem speculation appears to 



32 NATURE OF INDUCTIVE INFERENCE. 

be converging, is advocated with great ability in the works 
of Mr. Herbert Spencer ^. 

The student who wishes for further information on the 
questions discussed in this Note is referred to Dugald 
Stewart's Philosophy of the Human Mind^ Part II. ch. v. 
§ 2 ^" (' Of that Permanence or Stability in the order of 
Nature which is presupposed in our Reasonings concerning 
Contingent Truths'); Reid's Intellectual Powers, Essay VI. 
ch. vi ; Reid's Active Powers, Essay I. ch. iv ; Hamilton's 
Supplementary Dissertations to Reid's Works, Note A, § 3, 
Note Q; Hamilton's Lectures on Metaphysics, Lectures 
XXXIX, XL ; James Mill's Analysis of the Phenomena 
of the Human Mind, ch. xi ; Mill's Logic, Book III. 
ch. iii-v, xxi ; Mansel's Prolegomena Logica, ch. v ; Man- 
sel's Metaphysics, Section on Necessary Truths ; Mill on 
Hamilton, ch. xvi ; Lewes' History of Philosophy, Article 
on Kant; Bain's Moral and Mental Science, Book II. 
ch. vi, with Appendix B ; Herbert Spencer's Principles of 
Psychology, Part IV. The student, in employing these 
references, must be careful to distinguish between what 
relates to the Law of Universal Causation (sometimes 
called the Principle of Causality) and the Law of the 
Uniformity of Nature. The two Laws, as already noticed, 
are not always distinguished with sufl&cient care. 

^ Sec especially his work on the Principles of Pyscbologyj Part IV. 
^ In Sir W. Hamilton's edition of Stewart's Works, the corresponding 
reference, is Part II. Subdivision I. ch. ii. section 4, subsection 2. 



CHAPTER II. 
Of Processes subsidiary to Induction. 

OF the various mental processes subsidiary to In- 
duction proper, it will be sufficient for our purpose to 
discuss Observation and Experiment, Classification (in- 
cluding Nomenclature and Terminolog}'), and Hypo- 
thesis. 

§1. Of Observation and Experiment, 

These words are now so familiar, that they hardly 
require any explanation. To observe is to watch with 
attention phenomena as they occur, to experiment (or, to 
adopt more ordinary language, to perform an experiment^ 
is, not only to observe, but also to place the phenomena 
under peculiarly favourable circumstances, as a pre- 
liminary to observation. Thus, every experiment im- 
plies an observation, but it also implies something more. 
Jn an experiment, I arrange or create the circumstances 
imder which I wish to make my observation. Thus, if 
two bodies are falling to the ground, and I attend to the 
phenomenon, I am said to observe it, but, if I place the 
bodies imder the exhausted receiver of an air-pump, or 
cause them to be dropped under any special circum- 
stances whatever, I may be said not only to make an 

D 



34 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

observation, but also to perform an experiment. Bacon 
has not inaptly compared experiment with the torture of 
witnesses ^. Mr. Mill distinguishes between the two pro- 
cesses, by saying that in observation we Jind our instance 
in nature, in experiment we Tnake it, by an artificial ar- 
rangement of circumstances. *When, as in astronomy, 
we endeavour to ascertain causes by simply watching 
their effects, we observe ; when, as in our laboratories, we 
interfere arbitrarily with the causes or circumstances of 
a phenomenon, w^ are said to experiment^* 

As Observation often involves little or no conscious 
effort, while Experiment always implies an, artificial 
arrangement of circumstances, it might be expected that 
the general employment of the former for scientific pur- 
poses would long precede that of the latter. And this 
supposition is confirmed by the History of Science. 
Though it is false to afl&rm that Experiment was never 
employed by the Greeks', its general neglect was cer- 
tainly one cause of the little progress made by them in 
the physical sciences. 

^ * Quemadmodum enim in civilibus ingenium cujusque, et occultus 
animi affectuumque sensus, melius elicitur, cum quis in perturbation« 
ponitur, quam alias : simili modo, et occulta naturae magis se produrit 
per vexationes artium, quam cum cursu suo meant.' Nov. Org., Bk. I. 
Aph. xcviii. 

^ Thomson and Tait's Natural Pbiloscpby, vol. i. § 369. 

* For a refutation of this popular misconception, see Mr. Lewes* work 
on AristotUy ch. vi. Mr Lewes, however, seems to me not sufficiently to 
recognise the slight extent to which Experiment was employed in ancient 
as compared with modem times. 



OBSERVATION AND EXPERIMENT. 35 

In the attempt to ascertain the effect of a given cause, 
there can be no question of the general superiority of 
Experiment over Observation. To be able to vary the 
circumstances as we choose, to produce the phenomenon 
under investigation in the precise degree which is most 
convenient to us, and as frequently as we wish to com- 
bine it with other phenomena or to isolate it altogether, 
are such obvious advantages that it is not necessary to 
insist upon them. Without the aid of artificial experi- 
ment, it would have been impossible, for instance, to 
ascertain the laws of falling bodies. To disprove the old 
theory that bodies fall in times inversely proportional to 
their weights, it was necessary to try the experiment ; to 
be able to afiirm with certainty that all bodies, if moving 
in a non-resisting medium, would fall to the earth through 
equal vertical spaces in equal times, it was essential to 
possess the means of removing altogether the resisting 
medium by some such contrivance as that of the air- 
pump. In some of the sciences, such as Chemistry, the 
Sciences of Heat, Light, and Electricity, it is next 
to impossible, at least in their inductive stage, to ad- 
vance a single step without the aid of Experiment. No 
amoimt of mere Observation would ever have enabled 
us to detect the chemical elements of which various 
bodies are composed, or to ascertain the effects of these 
elements in their pure state. Even when Observation 
alone reveals to us a fact of nature. Experiment is often 
necessary in order to give precision to our knowledge. 
That the metals are fusible, and that some are fusible at 

D 2 



36 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION, 

a lower temperature than others, is a fact which we can 
conceive to have been obtruded upon man's observation, 
but the precise temperatiu-e at which each metal begins 
to change the solid for the liquid condition could be 
learnt only by artificial experiment 

But, though, in ascertaining the effect of a given cause. 
Experiment is a far more potent instrument than Ob- 
servation, the latter process is also available, and is 
frequently of the greatest service. Thus, the Science of 
Medicine equally avails itself,, for this purpose, both of 
observations and experiments. The scientific physician 
will not only fry the effects of different medicaments, 
different modes of diet, and the like, but he will also 
watch the effects on the organic system of various occu- 
pations, habits, and pursuits. In some cases even, as 
in all astronomical and many physiological phenomena, 
the only means open to us of ascertaining the effect of 
a given cause is Observation. If we wish to ascertain 
the various phenomena attendant on a shower of meteors, 
or a total eclipse of the sun, we must wait till the shower 
of meteors occurs or the total eclipse takes place. If 
we wish to learn the effects of the lesion of a particular 
part of the nervous system, we must generally wait till 
an instance offers itself; there are many experiments too 
dangerous and too costly to be made, at least in the case 
of man. 

While, however, both Observation and Experiment are 
available in ascertaining the effects of a given cause, 
in the reverse process of ascertaining the cause of a 



OBSERVATION AND EXPERIMENT. 37 

given effect, Observation alone is open to us. *We 
can take a cause/ says Mr. Mill, *and try what it will 
produce; but we cannot take an effect, and try' [that 
is, experimentally], * what it will be produced by. We 
can only watch till we see it produced, or are enabled 
to produce it by accident.' In those cases, consequently, 
in which effects alone are patent to us, and the causes 
are concealed from our view, we are compelled to have 
recourse to Observation. A new disease makes its ap- 
pearance : the mode of its action, and the conditions 
favourable or unfavourable to its diffusion, can only be 
learned by a careful observation and comparison of 
cases. 

It will readily be seen that those Sciences which de- 
pend wholly or mainly on Observation are, as inductive 
sciences, at a great disadvantage compared with those 
in which it is possible largely to employ Experiment. 
Where we wish to ascertain the effect of a given cause, 
and we cannot make the instances for ourselves, the 
want of appropriate and definite instances will often 
completely baffle us. And, though the cause of a given 
effect can only be learned by Observation, this is gene- 
rally an enquiry of extreme difficulty, requiring to be 
supplemented by experiment, or the actual production 
of the given effect by the supposed cause, before we can 
be certain that it has been conducted with the required 
accuracy. Thus, mere observation of the electrical phe- 
nomena which we witness in the heavens could never 
have given us the Science of Electricity. The experiments 



38 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

which we may conduct in an hour are often worth a 
century spent in observations. 

In the Science of Astronomy this defect is more than 
compensated for by the extreme simplicity of the phe- 
nomena, the heavenly bodies being regarded by us, not 
in themselves, but only in their mutual relations. Hence, 
we are, at a comparatively early stage, enabled to apply 
the Deductive Method, and to solve the problems of 
Astronomy by mathematical calculations. But in the 

very complex Science of Physiology this resource is not 

* 

open to us, and hence the backwardness of those de- 
partments of physiological science in which direct ex- 
periment is not available. Any animal or vegetable 
organism is so complex, the data are so numerous, and 
bear to each other so many different relations, that, 
hitherto, it has been found impracticable to subject 
physiology, at least in its details, to a deductive treat- 
ment. In social and political speculations, the want of 
experiment is, to some extent, supplied by statistics. A 
social or political experiment is generally as impracticable 
as an experiment in physiology, and the danger with 
which it is attended is often incomparably greater. But 
the number of observations open to us in these enquiries 
(as, for instance, in respect to crime, education, trade, 
taxation, &c.) is often very large, and, by carefully 
comparing and systematising them, we may frequently 
detect some relation between two circumstances which 
enables us, with great probability, to infer that one has 
something to do with the production of the other. We 



OBSERVATION AND EXPERIMENT. 39 

are here, however, trenching on the province of those 
chapters which treat more peculiarly of inductive inference. 

The following Rules may be laid down for the right 
conduct of Observations and Experiments : — 

Rule I. They must be precise. It is often of the 
utmost importance to notice the exact time at which 
an event occurs, the length of its duration, the position 
of an object in space, its relation to surrounding objects, 
and the like. We are all acquainted with the prime im- 
portance of precision of detail in legal evidence ; it is no 
less indispensable in scientific research. For the purpose 
of enabling us to attain this object, various instruments 
and methods have been invented. As instances of these 
may be given, amongst instruments, the telescope, the 
microscope, the thermometer, the barometer, measures 
of various kinds, the balance, the dial, the clock, the 
watch, the chronometer, the vernier, the goniometer, the 
galvanometer, the thermo-electric pile ; amongst methods, 
the decimal system of notation, fractions both vulgar 
and decimal, the divisions of time, the various con- 
trivances for the measurement of space, the method of 
double-weighing, the method of least squares, the per- 
sonal equation in astronomical observations. To these 
instances might be added numerous others, but these 
will be sufficient to show the great aid derived by what 
may be called the natural methods of observation from 
artificial contrivances. The Thermometer and the Method 
of Double- Weighing furnish such striking exemplifica- 
tions of the assistance thus derived, that, though they 



40 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

are probably familiar to most of our readers, it may be 
desirable to explain them, one as an example of an 
instmment, the other of a method. 

The Thermometer (it is not necessary here to describe 
the different kinds of thermometers) is a contrivance for 
determining the degree of temperature, irrespective of 
the mode in which it aflfects individual organisms. As 
our sensibility varies considerably imder diflferent circum- 
stances, so that what at one time affects us with the 
sensation of hot will at another affect us with that of 
cold, the sense of touch cannot be depended upon for 
giving us accurate measurements of temperature. But 
the fact that an augmentation of temperature, with cer- 
tain rare exceptions (to be noticed hereafter), expands 
the bodies subject to its influence furnishes us with such 
a means of measurement. We take a substance which 
notably exemplifies the power of heat in expansion, such 
as mercury, alcohol, or, where it is necessary to ensure 
great precision, atmospheric air carefully prepared, and, 
by confining it within a tube, and marking off a scale 
of measurements along the side, we are enabled, by 
noting the degree of expansion of the substance in the 
tube, to estimate, at least approximately, the exact degree 
of temperature in the atmosphere or any other body, the 
conditions of which we are investigating. 

The method of Double- Weighing is peculiarly simple 
and ingenious. It is a contrivance for remedying any 
possible defects in the construction of the Balance. The 
body to be weighed and the standard weight are sue- 



OBSERVATION AND EXPERIMENT. 41 

r 

cessively placed in the same scale, and balanced by a 
third body, so that there can be no question of their 
exactly balancing each other, whatever may be the imper- 
fections of the balance in which they are weighed. 

It frequently happens, however, that a single observa- 
tion may greatly mislead us. I may be in a district at 
one time, and find the air very temperate and agreeable ; 
the next time I come, it may be peculiarly hot, or chill, 
or. moist. I may see a man, at the first shot, hit his 
mark ; but at the subsequent shots, he may fire very wide 
of it. Hence the importance, whenever there is any 
liability to error, of taking an average of observations. 
If a sufficient number of observations be taken, there is 
every probability that an error in one direction will be 
compensated by an error in the other, and that an ave- 
rage, derived from all the observations, will approximate 
much more nearly to the truth than any single observa- 
tion is likely to do. Thus, if I wish to ascertain the true 
character of the climate at any particular place, the obser- 
vations I consult must extend over a considerable number 
of years ; if I wish to estimate truly the skill of the marks- 
man, I must watch, not a single shot, but many successive 
ones. The average, it is true, is liable to error, but any 
single observation is much more so. There is hardly 
any department of science, depending upon observation, 
in which, if it be our object to obtain precision, this 
method is not indispensable *. 

* The student who may wish for further information in connection 
with Rule I. is referred to Dr. Whewell's Novum Organon Renovatum, 



42 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

Rule II. But, though it is necessary to be precise in 
our observations and experiments, it is also important, 
in order to avoid distraction and waste of time, to attend 
only to the material circumstances of the case we are in- 
vestigating. A physician, for instance, in prescribing for 
his patient, would not now think it necessary to take an 
observation of the planets, nor would a chemist, in gather- 
ing herbs for his decoctions, think it of any consequence 
to notice the phase of the moon. A caution should, how- 
ever, be added. Before neglecting any circumstance in 
our observations, it is of the utmost importance to have 
ascertained beyond doubt that it is not material to the 
subject of our enquiries*. To neglect this caution would 
be a violation of the first Rule. 

Rule III. The circumstances under which an observa- 
tion or experiment is made should, except in the very 
simplest cases, be varied as much as possible. A phy- 
sician, in studying the character of a disease, will note its 

Bk. III. ch. ii., and Herschel's Discourse on the Study of Natural Pbi* 
losopbyt § 387-9. On the importance of taking an average of obser- 
vations, see Herschel's Discourse^ § 226-30. 

^ The neophyte in science requires to be reminded that observations 
which might at first be supposed to be immaterial are often afterwards found 
to be amongst the circumstances most material to the enquiry. * Could 
anything' (says Dr. Rolleston, in his Address before the Medical Asso- 
ciation in 1868) * have seemed at first sight to be more impertinent, 
more otiosely curious and trifling, than to enquire during an epidemic of 
cholera what was the nature of the subsoil in the area it was ravaging, 
to what depth it was porous, and at what level the water was, and had 
been previously, standing in it ? Yet, as I think. Von Pcttenkofer has 
at last fought out and won his battle on these points.' 



OBSERVATION AND EXPERIMENT. 43 

effects on persons of different ages, constitutions, habits 
of life, and the like. An astronomical observer will not be 
content with a single observation of a newly-discovered 
comet, but will note the phenomena which attend it at va- 
rious stages in its passage through the heavens. A chemist 
will combine a newly-discovered element with the various 
other elements, and will try upon it the effect of heat, 
pressure, &c. It is, of course, implied that some discretion 
will be employed in the application of this Rule, and that 
the variation of circumstances will not be carried beyond 
the point at which there is some probability of its adding 
to our knowledge. 

Rule IV. The phenomenon under investigation should 
if possible be isolated from all other phenomena, or, at 
least, from all those which are likely to interfere with our 
study of it. In studying the eflfects of the action of 
gravity upon bodies, it was necessary- to exhaust the 
atmosphere and to withdraw the support, and, by thus 
insulating the phenomenon, to enable us to perceive how 
bodies behave when subject to the action of gravity only. 
A physician, in trying the effects of a new drug, will, at 
first at least, administer it alone, and not in combination 
with other drugs which might augment or counteract its 
influence on the system *. 

A beautiful instance of the isolation of a phenomenon 

* By observing the third of these rules we usually prepare our instances 
for the application of what will hereafter be explained as the Method of 
Agreement, and by observing the fourth for the application of what will 
hereafter be explained as the Method of Difference. 



44 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

is afforded whenever there occurs a total eclipse of the 
sun. As, on these occasions, the moon, by a curious 
coincidence, exactly covers, or rather more than covers, 
the sun's surface, and thus intercepts all light from it, we 
are able to see, what we see on no other occasion, cer- 
tain rose-coloured protuberances, projecting, as it were, 
from the dark edge of the moon, but really belonging to 
the sun. The real nature of these *red flames* was long 
a matter of dispute, but it seems now to be conclusively 
settled that they are portions of an atmosphere of incan- 
descent hydrogen in which the sun is enveloped, and 
which shoots out in these flames to a distance estimated 
at not less than forty or fifty thousand miles. Had it not 
been for the insulation of the phenomenon thus produced 
for us by the intervention of the moon, we should have 
been ignorant of their existence. Here, to use a bold 
metaphor, we might say that Nature herself performs an 
experiment for us^. 

When it is impossible entirely to isolate a phenomenon, 
it is sometimes possible so far to diminish the action of 
the concomitant circumstances as to be able accurately 
or approximately to calculate the effect, if they were alto- 
gether absent. Thus, we can never altogether remove 
the influence of friction on a moving body, but we can 

■^ A method has recently been devised by which these protuberances 
may be observed at any time when the sun is shining. Till quite re- 
cently, however, a total eclipse of the sun afforded the only occasion for 
observing them, and, if it had not been for the attention thus drawn to 
them, they would probably never have been discovered. 



CLASSIFICATION. 45 

SO far diminish it as to be able to say what the effect 
would be were no such influence at work. We cannot 
altogether eliminate the influence of extraneous circum- 
stances on a patient subject to medical regime, but, by 
due care, we may minimise the excitement, fatigue, ennui, 
or other unfavourable conditions which might interfere 
with our treatment. 

The circumstances under which we perform our experi- 
ments being more in our own power than those under 
which we conduct our observations, it is obvious that 
the foregoing rules, and especially the third and fourth, 
can be more easily observed in experiments than in 
observations. 

§ 2. On Classification^ Nomenclature, and Terminology, 

(i) Of Classification. 

A classification, in the widest sense of the term, is a 
division, or a series of divisions and subdivisions ^. The 
process of classifying our own thoughts or feelings, or 
the actions of ourselves or others, or the external objects 
which surround us, is one of the most constant occupa- 
tions of the mind. Thus, we are perpetually dividing 
outward objects into those which are useful or those 
which are useless or noxious to us ; those which are useful 
into such as are within and such as are beyond our power 
to attain ; those which are useful and which it is within our 

' See Deductive Logic, Part II. ch. viii. 



46 PROCESSES SUBSIDFARY TO INDUCTION. 

power to attain into such as are to be sought at once, 
and those the effort to appropriate which may be more 
advantageously postponed,— -each of these divisions ad- 
mitting of ahnost infinite subdivision. In fact, as has 
frequently been remarked, every attribution of a general 
name implies an act of division or classification. 
When we speak of a horse, we are dividing all objects 
into those which are horses and those which are not. 
When we speak of a bay horse, we are superadding to 
this division the subdivision of horses into bay horses and 
those of any other colour. 

But the process of Classification of which we are about 
to treat, though the same in kind with that which we 
employ in the affairs of ordinary life, is of a much more 
complex and systematic character. The great difference 
is that, whereas in the affairs of ordinary life we generally 
classify objects with reference to some one principle, that 
principle varying according to the particular purpose we 
happen to have in view (thus we classify horses according 
to their colour, their breed, their strength, &c., each classi- 
fication being suggested by some distinct purpose), a 
scientific classification must take account of all the points 
of difference which are in any way likely to facilitate 
the scientific investigation of the group. The purport of 
the science being defined, the classification must be based, 
not on one or two characters, selected arbitrarily, but on 
the entire assemblage of characters which the science in- 
vestigates. Thus, if Botany be defined as the science 
which investigates the organisation (including under that 



CLA SSIFICA TION. 4 7 

. term the form, structure, and functions) of plants, a bota- 
nical classification, in order to be strictly scientific, must 
not omit to take into account any part of that organisa- 
tion. But it is evident that such a requirement would 
produce endless confusion, unless we could discover some 
mode of subordinating the characters, so as to make the 
more important points of diflference the basis of the higher 
divisions in the series. Hence we see already that a 
scientific classification must be guided by at least two 
principles, a review of all the characters or distinguishing 
marks, so far as they are known and so far as they fall 
within the scope of the science, and a subordination of 
these characters one to another. To these principles 
others will subsequently be added. 

Before proceeding to the attempt to ascertain induc- 
tively facts of co-existence or causation amongst a vast 
mass of phenomena, it is often highly important, if not 
essential, to arrange these phenomena in groups, as well 
as to determine the order in which these groups them- 
selves shall be arranged. Hence the importance of laying 
down correct rules for Classification in a System of 
Inductive Logic. It is exclusively as subsidiary to In- 
duction that we shall here consider the subject of Classi- 
fication. 

A scientific Classification, regarded as subsidiary to 
Induction employed for scientific purposes, may be de- 
fined as A Series of Divisions, so arranged as best to 

facilitate the complete and separate study of the several 
groups which are the result of the divisions, as well as of 



48 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

the entire subject under investigation. * The general pro- 
blem of classification/ says Mr. Mill^ *in reference to 
these [namely, scientific] purposes, may be stated as 
follows : To provide that things shall be thought of in 
such groups, and those groups in such an order, as will 
best conduce to the remembrance and to the ascertain- 
ment of their laws/ 

The sciences of Botany and Zoology are rightly re- 
garded as furnishing the best examples of Scientific Clas- 
sification. The excellence of the classifications which 
they present may be referred to two reasons. The first 
is the extraordinary multiplicity of the different kinds 
of animals and plants which are found on the surface of 
the globe: this has, from the earliest times, exercised 
man's ingenuity in the attempt to name them and reduce 
them to order. The second reason may be found in the 
imperfection of these sciences in their present condition : 
the difl&culty, amounting almost to impossibility, of dis- 
covering laws of succession, or, in other words, relations 
of cause and effect, in the animal and vegetable kingdoms 
has naturally led scientific enquirers to concentrate their 
attention on the far easier task of describing and ar- 
ranging the objects themselves. Mineralogy, though its 
classifications are less systematic and complete, is also, 
in the present state of the science, mainly occupied in 
attempting the work of classification. 

The best means, perhaps, of making the student ac- 
quainted with the nature of scientific classification is to 

» MiU's Logic, Bk. IV. ch. vii. § i. 



CLA SSIFICA TION. 49 

compare the method of natural classification (which aims 
at being strictly scientific) with that of artificial classifica- 
tion (which, so far as it is artificial, is not scientific), giving 
illustrations from the sciences of Botany and Zoology. 
An examination of the natural system will enable us to 
lay down certain rules for scientific classification, and we 
shall conclude with such remarks as may seem necessary in 
order to preserve the student from erroneous impressions. 
A natural system of Classification aims at classifying 
objects according to the whole of their resemblances and 
differences, so far as these are recognised by the science 
in whose service the classification is made. But amongst 
these resemblances and differences some are found to be 
invariably attended by a number of others, and conse- 
quently these, as the more important^ are selected as the 
characters by which to discriminate the higher divisions 
of the series, the less important characters being, through- 
out the whole series, subordinated to the more important. 
This successive subordination of characters and the con- 
sequent coincidence of the groups formed by our classi- 
fications with what appear to be the great divisions of 
nature are the peculiarities which mainly distinguish a 
natural system. An artificial system, on the other hand, 
is one which selects arbitrarily some point of difference 
amongst the objects to be classified, and then, so far as 
possible, makes this or similar points the basis of its 
classifications. No system, however, as we shall see pre- 
sently, is purely artificial. Though of little use, except 
as a preliminary effort, for the purposes of science, an 

E 



50 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

artificial system possesses one great advantage. As it 
bases its divisions, where possible, on some one property, 
and that generally something which at once strikes the 
eye (one of the earliest of the modern attempts to classify 
plants took for its basis the form of the corolla), it is 
peculiarly easy of application, and can be much more 
readily learnt than a natural system. It thus often serves 
the purposes of a key, by which we may easily discover 
the place of a group in a natural system. We now pro- 
ceed to offer illustrations. 

In Botany, the most celebrated artificial system is that 
known as the Linnaean, though Linnaeus also did much 
towards the establishment of a natural system. In this 
system, which was a great advance on preceding artificial 
systems, the main basis of classification is the number of 
stamens and pistils which are to be found in the flowering 
plant. This character is, however, to some extent 
modified by other considerations, such as the relative 
lengths of the stamens, the shape of the fruit, &c. ; so far 
as these modifications are admitted, the Linnaean system 
approaches to a natural system. The annexed Tables 
(extracted from Balfour's Manual of Botany^^) will give 
the student some idea of the manner in which the Classes 
(higher divisions) and the Orders (divisions intermediate 
between the Classes and Genera) are constituted accord- 
ing to the Linnaean system. It should be premised that 
the stamens are the male organs, and the pistils the 
female organs of a plant. 

^' §§7J6. 7'7- 



CLASSIFICATION. 51 



Tabxtlar View of the Classes of the Linnjean System. 

A. Flowers present, or evident Stamens and Pistils (Phanerogamia). 
I. Stamens and Pistil in every flower. 
I. Stamens Free, 

a. Stamens of equal length, or not differing in certain propor- 
tions ; 
in number I Class I. Monandria. 

— 2 II. Diandria. 

— 3 III. Triandria. 

— 4 IV. Tetrandria. 

— 5 .. • • • V. Pentandria. 

— 6 VL Hezandria. 

— 7 VII. Heptandria. 

— 8 VIII. Octandria. 

— 9 IX. Enneandria. 

— lo X. Decandria. 

— 12-19 XI. Dodecandria. 

— 20 J inserted on Calyx — XII. Icosandria. 
or more J on Receptacle XIII. Polyandria. 

b. Stamens of different lengths ; 

two long and two short XIV. Didynamia. 

four long and two short XV. Tetradynamia. 

2. Stamens united ; 

by Filaments in one bundle XVI. Monadelphia. 

in two bundles XVII. Diadelphia. 

in more than two bundles XVIII. Polyadelphia. 

by Anthers (Compound flowers) XIX. Syngenesia. 

with Pistil on a Colunm XX. Gynandria. 

II. Stamens and Pistil in different flowers ; 

on the same Plant XXI. Monoecia. 

on different Plants XXII. DIcecia. 

III. Stamens and Pistil in the same or in 

different flowers on the same or on ^ XXIII. Polygamia. 

different plants 

B. Flowers absent, or Stamens and Pistils not 
evident 



} 

I XXrV. Cryptogamia. 



E 2 



^2 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 



The Classes are sub-divided into Orders, as will be 
seen from the next Table, on a less uniform plan than 
that on which they themselves were constituted. 

Tabular View of the Orders of the Linnjean System. 



Class. I. 

II. 

III. 

IV. 

V. 

VI. 

VII. 

VIII. 

IX. 

X. 

XL 

XII. 

XIII. 



Monogynia ^^ i Free Style. 

Digynia 2 Free Styles. 

Trigynia 3 — 

Tetragynia 4 — 

Pentagynia 5 — 

Hexagynia 6 — 

Heptagynia 7 — ^ 

Octogynia 8 — 

Enneagynia 9 — 

Decagynia 10 — 

Dodecagynia 1 2-19 — 

Polygynia 20 and upwards. 



( Gymnospermia Fruit formed by four Achsenia. 

XIV. < Angiospermia Fruit, a two-celled Capsule with 

( many seeds. 

yy f Siliculosa Fruit, a Silicula. 

* \ Siliquosa Fruit, a Siliqua. 



XVI. 
XVII. ^Triandria, Decandria, &c. (number of Stamens), as in Classes. 



^•1 
XVIII. J 



Polygamia ^qualis. . . . Florets all hermaphrodite. 

Superflua. . . . Florets of the disk hermaphrodite, 

those of the ray pistilliferous and 
fertile. 

Frustranea . . Florets of the disk hermaphrodite, 

XIX. -l those of the ray neuter. 

Necessaria. . . Florets of the disk staminiferous, 

those of the ray pistilliferous. 

Segregata . . . Each floret having a separate in- 
volucre. 

Monogamia Anthers united, flowers compound. 

^* It must not be supposed tliat all the Orders, Monogynia, &c., exist 
in each of the first thirteen Classes. When an Order is absent, the next 
Order which is present takes its place in the numerical arrangement. 
Thus, if the Order Trigynia be absent, and the next Order which is pre- 
sent be Tetragynia, as in Class IV, this latter will rank as the third 
Order. 



XX. 

XXI. 
XXII. 



XXIII. 



XXIV. ^ 



CLASSIFICATION. 53 

Monandria, Diandria, &c. (number of Stamens), as in the 

Classes. 

' Monoecia Hermaphrodite, staminiferous, and 

pistiliferous flowers on the same 
plant. 

Dicecia on two plants. 

Tricecia on three plants. 

Filices Ferns. 

Musci Mosses. 

Hepaticse Liverworts. 

Lichenes Lichens. 

Algx Sea-weeds. 

Fungi Mushrooms. 



* Even as an artificial method/ says Professor Balfour ^^, 
* this system has many imperfections. If plants are not in 
full flower, with all the stamens and styles perfect, it is 
impossible to determine their class and order. In many 
instances, the different flowers on the same plant vary as 
regards the number of the stamens. Again, if carried 
out rigidly, it would separate in many instances the 
species of the same genus ; but as Linnaeus did not wish 
to break up his genera, which were founded on natural 
aflMties, he adopted an artifice by which he kept all the 
species of a genus together. Thus, if in a genus nearly 
all the species had both stamens and pistils in every 
flower, while one or two were monoecious or dioecious, 
he put the name of the latter in italics, in the classes and 
orders to which they belonged according to his method, 
and referred the student to the proper genus for the 
description.' 

The species of the Linnaean system coincide with those 

" Balfcur*8 Manual of Botany, § 718. 



54 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

of the natural system. The same is mostly the case with 
the genera, or next higher divisions. The Linnaean 
system is, therefore, far from being purely artificial. In 
fact, when we come to the lower groups of vegetables 
(genera and species), we are compelled to discriminate 
them one from another by a multiplicity of characters, so 
that a purely artificial system of botany would be im- 
possible. 

The framers of natural systems of botany, instead of 
selecting some one character, such as the number of 
stamens and pistils, as the basis of the higher divisions, at- 
tempt to discover a number of characters, any one of which, 
if employed as the instrument of division, would give the 
same results as any of the others. This coincidence of 
divisions founded on various characters is a proof that we 
have reached some real distinction in nature. The main 
division of plants into cellular and vascular, or acoty- 
ledonous and cotyledonous, and the sub-division of vas- 
cular or cotyledonous plants into monocotyledonous and 
dicotyledonous, furnish remarkable instances of such 
a coincidence, and may consequently be regarded as cor- 
responding with grand divisions in nature itself. 

*In taking a survey of the Vegetable Kingdom, some 
plants are found to be composed of cells only, and are 
called Cellular ; while others consist of cells and vessels, 
especially spiral vessels, and are denominated Vascular, 
If the embryo is examined, it is found in some cases to 
have cotyledons or seed-lobes, in other cases to want 
them; and thus some plants are cotyledonous^ others 



CLA SSIFICA TION. 55 

dcoiyUdonous ; the former being divisible into monocotyle- 
donous, having one cotyledon, and dicotyledonous, having 
two [or more] cotyledons. The radicle, or young root 
of acotyledons, is helerorhizal, that of monocotyledons is 
endorhizalf that of dicotyledons, exorhizal. When the 
stems are taken into consideration, it is seen that marked 
differences occur here also, acotyledons being acrogenous, 
monocotyledons endogenous, and dicotyledons exogenous. 
The venation of leaves, parallel, reticulated, or forked, 
establishes the same great natural divisions ; and similar 
results are obtained from a consideration of the flowers, 
monocotyledons and dicotyledons being phanerogamous , 
and acotyledons crypiogamous! 

* Thus, the following grand natural divisions are arrived 
at: — 

I. Cellular. ..Acotyledonous. Heterorhizal. Acrogenous. i ^^TP^O" 

I gamous. 

( Monocotyledonous. Endorhizal. Endogenous. )Phanero- 

' (Dicotyledonous. Exorhizal. Exogenous. ) gamous . 

Having established these Primary Divisions of the 
vegetable kingdom, the botanist, guiding himself as far as 
possible by the same principles as those on which the 
primary divisions were formed, proceeds to divide and 
sub-divide till at last he arrives at species, which are 
generally defined to be collections of individuals so nearly 
resembling each other that they may be supposed to be 
descended from a common stock. Thus, the Class 
* Dicotyledones or Exogenae ' is sub-divided into four sub- 

" Balfour's Manual of Botany, §§ 723, 724. 



^6 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

classes, one of which is the * Thalamiflorae/ characterised 
as having * calyx and corolla present, petals distinct and 
inserted into the thalamus or receptacle, stamens hy- 
pogynous/ This sub-class is divided into a number of 
orders (sixty in Professor Balfour's Manual)^ one of which 
is Hypericaceae, the Tutsan or St. John's-wort family, 
thus described: — 

' Sepals 4-5, separate or united, persistent, usually with glandular dots, 
unequal ; aestivation imbricated. Petals 4-5, oblique, often with black 
dots, aestivation contorted. Stamens hypogynous, indefinite in number ; 
generally polyadelphous, very rarely 10, and monadelphous or distinct ; 
filaments filiform ; anthers bilocular, with longitudinal dehiscence ; car- 
pels 2-5, united round a central or basal placenta ; styles the same num- 
ber as the carpels, usually separate ; stigmas capitate or simple. Fruit 
either fleshy or capsular, multilocular, and multivalvular, rarely unilocu- 
lar. Seeds usually indefinite in number, minute, anatropal, usually ex- 
albuminous; embryo usually straight. — Herbaceous plants, shrubs or 
trees, with exstipulate entire leaves, which are usually opposite and 
dotted. Flowers often yellow.' 

In this order th^re are fifteen known genera, one of 
which is the Hypericum, which is thus described in 
Irvine's Handbook 0/ British Plants : — 

* H3rpericum, St. John*s-wort. Herbaceous plants or shrubs, with 
opposite, simple, entire leaves, which are usually furnished with pellucid 
dots (reservoirs of essential oil). Sepals five, free or united at the base, 
ovate, slightly unequal, permanent. Petals as many as the sepals, 
obtuse, spreading. Stamens indefinite, combined at the base into three 
or five sets, with small roundish anthers. Ovary with three-five cells 
or carpels and as many styles, with simple stigmas. Fruit capsular, 
rarely baccate, three-five-celled, with numerous seeds.* 

This genus is divided into sub-genera or sections, one 
of which is thus described : 



CLA SSIFICA TION. 5 J 

* Steins herbaceous. Stamens in three parcels (triadelphous). Styles 
three. Capsule three-celled, three-valved.* 

This sub-genus or section is again divided into sub- 
sections, one of which is characterized as having * stems 
round, sepals with ciliary glands/ This sub-section con- 
tains amongst its species the well-known Hypericum 
Pulchrum, * Elegant St. John's-wort,' thus described : 

* Stems erect, bent at the base, round, glabrous, simple or branching. 
Leaves ovate, clasping, coriaceous, smooth, with numerous translucent 
dots. Flowers in opposite panicled cymes. Sepals obovate, roundisb, 
with a point, ciliated, with nearly sessile glands. Petals oblong, ribbed, 
with black sessile glands ^*.* 

The first peculiarity which strikes us in these descrip- 
tions is the large number of characters which is employed 
in constituting even the higher divisions of the series. 
Instead of describing merely the number and distribution 
of the stamens, as in the Linnaean system, we have, even in 
the description of the Order, a reference to almost every 
part of the plant. We next notice the much greater 
definiteness which the characters assume, as we descend 
lower in the series. Thus, to take the sepals as an in- 
stance, the description of the sub-class simply informs 
us of the presence of a calyx, while each successive divi- 
sion (except the sub-genus) gives us more and more 
definite information as to the number, position, form, &c. 
of the sepals which constitute the calyx. Again, we 
observe that, in the lower divisions, the stem, leaves, 
sepals, and petals are the characters which are brought 

" See Irvine's Handbook of British Plants, under Order CIII. 



58 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

into greatest prominence, whereas the stamens and the 
various parts of the pistil (the carpels, styles, and stigmas), 
which are employed in the higher divisions, disappear 
from the lower, as no longer affording grounds of differ- 
ence. Now the stamens and pistil, inasmuch as any 
peculiarity in them is generally accompanied by a larger 
number of peculiarities in other parts of the plant, are 
usually of far more importance than the corolla (petals) 
and calyx (sepals), and therefore it is reasonable to suppose 
that the grounds of difference furnished by them would 
be likely to be exhausted in the higher divisions. At the 
same time we see that, in the instance we have taken, the 
sepals and petals furnish grounds of difference at a very 
early stage of the classification, and consequently that 
even the less important characters are often used co- 
ordinately with others to determine the higher divisions. 

In Zoology, the advantage of a natural over an artificial 
classification is more readily recognised than in Botany, 
the structure and functions of animals being more fa- 
miliar and apparent than those of plants. A division of 
animals, for instance, which adopted the number of limbs 
as its sole distinguishing character, and thus brought 
together, as quadrupeds ^ the ox and the frog, would be so 
absurd on the face of it, as to be rejected at once. * No 
arrangement of animals,' says Dr. Whewell ^®, ' which, in 
a large number of instances, violated strong and clear 
natural aflSnities, would be tolerated because it answered 

'* History of the Inductive Sciences^ Bk. XVI. ch. vii. 



CLA SSIFICA TION. 59 

the purpose of enabling us easily to find the name and 
place of the animal in the artificial system. Every system 
of Zoological arrangement may be supposed to aspire 
to be a natural system.' He then proceeds to give an 
instance of an attempt to constitute an artificial classifica- 
tion in the ichthyological branch of Zoology. *Bloch, 
whose ichthyological labours have been mentioned, fol- 
lowed in his great work the method of Linnaeus/ (who 
devoted much of his attention to the classification of 
animals as well as of plants.) * But towards the end of 
his life he had prepared a general system, founded upon 
one single numerical principle — the number of fins ; just 
as the sexual system of Linnaeus is founded upon the 
number of stamina : and he made his sub-divisions ac- 
cording to the position of the ventral and pectoral fins ; 
the same character which Linnaeus had employed for his 
primary division. He could not have done better, says 
Cuvier, if his object had been to turn into ridicule all 
artificial methods, and to show to what absurd combina- 
tions they may lead.' 

*By the natural meihodl says M. Milne Edwards^® 
(whose remarks on Zoological Classifications and the 
Primary Divisions and Classes of the Animal Kingdom 
are well worthy of the attention of all students of induc- 
tive logic), ' the divisions and subdivisions of the animal 

*• See Milne Edwards' Zoologie (in the Cours elementaire (Tbistoire 
naturelle), septifeme edition, §§ 364, 365. There is an English transla- 
tion of this work by Dr. R. Knox. I have followed it, except in a few 
places where it docs not accurately represent the original. 



6o PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

kingdom are founded on the whole of the characters fur- 
nished by each animal, arranged according to their degree 
of respective importance; thus, in knowing the place 
which the animal occupies, we also know the more re- 
markable traits of its organisation, and the manner in 
which its principal functions are exercised. 

* The rules to be observed in arriving at a natural clas- 
sification of the animal kingdom are of extreme simplicity, 
but often there is much diflSculty in the application. They 
may be reduced to two, for the object of the zoologist in 
establishing such a classification is, — 

' I St. To arrange animals in natural series, according 
to the degree of their respective affinities, — that is to say, 
to distribute them in such a manner that those species 
which most nearly resemble each other may occupy the 
nearest places, while the distance of two species from 
each other may, in some sort, be the measure of their 
non-resemblance. 

' 2nd. To divide and subdivide this series according 
to the principle of subordination of characters, — that is 
to say, by reason of the importance of the differences 
which these animals present between them.' 

The Primary Divisions of the animal kingdom, ac- 
cording to the natural system, are four, there being four 
types of structure and of nervous organisation, to which 
animal life conforms. 

* These four principal forms may be understood by a 
reference to four well-known animals — the dog, the cray- 
fish or lobster, the snail, the asterias or sea-star. 



CLASSIFICATION. 6 1 

*In order that the zoological classification might be a 
faithful representation of the more or less important 
modifications introduced into the structure of animals, it 
was necessary to distribute these beings into four prin- 
cipal groups or divisions; and this is, in fact, what 
Cuvier did. 

* The animal kingdom is divided into vertebrate animals, 
articulated or annulated animals, molluscs, and zoophytes. 

* The fundamental differences distinguishing these four 
primary divisions depend chiefly on the mode of arrange- 
ment of the different parts of the body and on the con- 
formation of the nervous system. It is easy to under- 
stand the importance of these two dominant characters : 
to feel and to move is the especial character of animal 
life, and these two functions belong to the nervous system. 
It might readily, then, be anticipated that the mode of 
conformation of this system would exert a powerful 
influence over the nature of animals, and would furnish 
characters of primary importance in classification. 

* The general disposition or mode of reimion of the 
'different parts of the body exercises an equally impor- 
tant influence, as modifying the localisation of the func- 
tions and the division of the physiological result ^'^! 

Vertebrate animals are thus described : 

' The verlehrate animals resemble man in the more important points 
of their structure ; almost all the parts of their bodies are in pairs, and 
disposed symmetrically on the two sides of a medial longitudinal plane ; 
their nervous system is highly developed, and is composed of nerves and 

" Mihie Edwards, §§ 372, 373. 



62 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

-ganglionic and of a brain and spinal marrow. To these we may add, 
that the principal muscles are attached to an internal skeleton, composed 
of separate pieces, connected together, and disposed so as to protect the 
more important organs, and to form the passive instruments of loco- 
motion ; that the more important part of this skeleton forms a sheath 
for the brain and spinal marrow, and results from the reunion of annular 
portions, called vertebrae ; that the apparatus for the circulation is very 
complete, and that the heart offers at least two distinct reservoirs ; that 
the blood is red; that the limbs are almost always four in number, 
and never more ; finally, that there exist distinct organs lodged in the 
head for sight, hearing, smell, and taste '*/ 

The Primary Division (embranchement) 'Vertebrate 
Animals ' is sub-divided into the five classes, Mammals, 
Birds, Reptiles, Batrachia, Fishes, of which Mammals 
are thus described : 

' Organs of lactation. Hot blood. Circulation complete, and heart 
with four cavities. Pulmonary respiration siipple. Lobes of the cere* 
helium reunited by an annular protuberance. Lower jaw articulated 
directly with the cranium. The body generally covered with hairs. 
Viviparous.* 

* There exist considerable differences amongst the 
mammalia, and these modifications of structure serve 
as the basis for the division of the class into groups^ 
of an inferior rank, called orders. Most of these groups 
are so distinct as to admit of no doubt in respect 
of their limits : they constitute, in fact, natural divisions ; 
but in others the line of demarcation is by no means so 
distinct. Thus a mammal may have points of resemblance 
so close to two groups as to render it almost indifferent 
to which it be referred. To some naturalists, differences 

" Milne Edwards, § 374. 



CLASSIFICATION. 63 

appear important which are disregarded by others, and 
hence a want of agreement on the subject of classification 
has always prevailed. 

* The method followed here is nearly the same as that 
proposed by Cuvier. It rests mainly on the differences 
mammals show in respect of their extremities and teeth, 
differences which always imply a crowd of others in 
habits, structm-e, and even intelligence. 

' Keeping in view the ensemble of these characters, the 
class mammalia may be divided into two groups, — the 
monodelphic and didelphic. 

* The monodelphic or monodelphian are the more nu- 
merous, and are distinguished chiefly by their mode of 
development. At birth they are already provided with all 
their organs, and before birth they derive their nomish- 
ment from the mother by means of a placenta. Their 
brain is more perfect than the didelphian, by the presence 
of a corpus callosum uniting the two cerebral hemispheres. 
Finally, the walls of the abdomen have no osseous sup- 
ports attached to the margins of the pelvis, as we find 
in the second great class of mammals. The mammals 
thus organised have been subdivided into two groups, — 
namely, ordinary mammals and pisciform mammals, 

*The ordinary mammals are organised principally to 
live on solid ground; the skin is provided with hairs. 
These animals are further subdivided into ten orders : the 
bimana, quadrumana, cheiroptera, insectivora, rodentia, 
edentata, camivora, amphibia, pachydermata, and rumi- 
nantia. The first eight of these orders have flexible 



64 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

fingers and toes, with nails covering only the dorsal aspect 
of the toe or finger, and comparatively small ; hence they 
have been called unguiculata ; the last two, — namely, the 
pachydermata and ruminantia, have the extremity of the 
finger and toe entirely enclosed in a hoof; they are thus 
called ungulaia, 

' The order bimana includes only man : in him alone 
the arms are destined for prehension, the limbs for pro-, 
gression and support in the erect attitude. Thus, his 
natural position on the soil is unmistakeably vertical. The 
teeth are of three kinds, and have their edges on the same 
plane ; they are frugivorous : finally, the brain is more per- 
fect, more highly developed, than in any other animal ^'.' 

Here the Order is coextensive with the Species, but 
usually the Order is divided into Genera, and each Genus 
into Species. Thus, the Order *Carnivora' is divided 
into the Genera * cat,' * hygena,' ' dog,' * bear,' &c. Again, 
the Genus * dog' comprises the dog properly so called, the 
wolf, and the fox. The genus * cat ' comprises not only 
the cat properly so called, but the tiger, lion, panther, &c. 

It may be as well to add an account of the characters 
which distinguish respectively the Order ' Carnivora,' the 
Genus * Felis,' and the Species * Leo,' in order to serve 
as an example or illustration of the manner in which these 
several degrees in the scale of Classification are usually 
described : — 

* The order of camivora is composed of ordinary unguiculated mam- 
mals ; the form of their dentition is complete, but they have no opposing 

^* Milne Edwards, § 409-412. 



CLASSIFICATION. 65 

thumb. According to the mode of life of these animals, their intestinal 
canal is short ; their jaws and their muscles strong, in order to seize and 
devour their prey ; their head from this circumstance seems large. The 
jaws are short, thus favouring their strength, and the form of the tem- 
poral-maxillary articulation proves that the teeth are made for tearing 
and cutting, not for grinding or masticating. The canine teeth are 
large, long, and very powerful ; the incisors, six in number in each jaw, 
small ; the molars, sometimes adapted merely for cutting, in others sur- 
mounted with rounded tubercles, presenting no conical points, arranged 
as in the insectivora. One of these molar teeth is usually much longer 
and more cutting than the others, and has therefore been called the car- 
nivorous molar tooth ; behind these (on each side) are one or two molars, 
almost flat, and between the carnivorous molar and the canine a variable 
number of false molars. The food of the animal, whether exclusively 
composed of flesh or mixed with other matters, may be judged of by the 
varying proportions of these cutting or tuberculated molars. 

* Animals of this order have generally the toes armed with claws 
adapted to hold and to tear their prey ; usually also they have no collar- 
bones.' 

The following are the characteristics of the genus 
*Felis/ and of the species * Leo :' — 

* Their jaws are short, and are acted on by muscles of extraordinary 
strength ; their retractile nails, concealed between the toes in a state of 
repose by means of elastic ligaments, are never blunted. Their toes are 
five in number on the anterior limbs, and four on those behind. Their 
hearing is exceedingly fine, and the best developed of all their senses. 
They see well by day and night, but they are not farsighted ; in some 
the pupil is elongated vertically, in others it is round. They make great 
use of the organ of smell ; they consult it before eating, and often when 
anything disturbs them. Their tongue is covered with homy and very 
rough points. Their coat is in general soft and fine, and the surface 
of the body very sensible to the touch ; their whiskers especially seem 
to be instruments of great sensibility. Though of prodigious vigour, 
they generally do not attack animals openly, but employ cunning and 
artifice. They never push their prey to flight, but watching by the 
margins of rivers and pools in covert, they spring at once on their victim. 

F 



66 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

* At the head of this genus stands the Hon, measuring frequently 
twelve feet in length, or over six feet to the setting on of the tail ; about 
three feet in height, and characterised by the square head, the tuft of 
hair terminating the tail, and in the male by the mane which flows from 
the head and neck ^.' 

The process by which the Zoologist constitutes the 
Primary Divisions of animal life, and then descends from 
these to the Species, is distinguished by the same pecu- 
liarities as those which we remarked in reviewing the 
natural classifications of the Botanist. In one step or 
other of the classification almost every known charac- 
teristic of a species will be found. As we descend the 
series, the characters gain in definiteness and, as a rule, 
lose in importance. Moreover, even in the higher divi- 
sions of the series, numerous characters are used, and 
those not always of great apparent importance. Thus, 
that *the body is generally covered with hairs' is one 
of the characters of Mammalia. 

The student will now be in a position to understand 
the rules which may be laid down for the right conduct 
of a Natural Classification. 

I. Not only the lower, but the higher groups of the 
series should be so constituted as to differ from one 
another by a multitude of characters. It is only when, 
as is the case in the primary divisions of Botany and 
Zoology, we arrive at the same divisions from a variety 
of different considerations, that we can feel assured that 
our groups really correspond with distinctions in Nature. 

» Milne Edwards, § 414. 



CLASSIFICATION. 67 

It is this coincidence^ in the higher groups of the series, 
of divisions formed on different principles, that distin- 
guishes a Natural from an Artificial Classification. 

II. The more important characters should be selected 
for the purpose of determining the higher groups. This 
is called the principle of the subordination of characters. 
But how are we to determine the relative importance 
of characters? *We must consider as the most im- 
portant attributes,' says Mr. Mill^^, 'those which contribute 
most, either by themselves or by their effects, to render 
the things like one another, and unlike other things; 
which give to the class composed of them the most 
marked individuality; which fill, as it were, the largest 
space in their existence, and would most impress the 
attention of a spectator who knew all their properties but 
was not specially interested in any/ This is perfectly 
true, but it seems to be hardly sufficiently definite. The 
following criteria may be proposed for the purpose of 
discriminating between the more and the less important 
properties of natural objects, (i.) A character which is 
found to furnish an invariable index to the possession 
of certain other characters is of more importance than 
a character which fiunishes no such index. Thus, the 
internal structure of an animal is of more importance than 
its size, and the mode of fructification of a plant than 
the colour of its flowers. (2.) Amongst such characters, 
a character is regarded as of more or less importance, 

» Mill's Logic, Bk. IV. ch. vii. § 2. 
F 2 



68 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

according as it accompanies a greater or smaller number 
of other differences. Thus, in the classification of ani- 
mals, the characters from which the classes imguiculata 
and ungulata are so called are of more importance than 
the form of the teeth, which is used in distinguishing the 
orders. For the same reason, the mode of growth of 
flowering plants (which leads to the distinction of en- 
dogenous and exogenous plants) is of far more im- 
portance, as a character, than the number of stamens 
or pistils. Hence, in constituting the higher divisions 
of a series we must look for those characters which are 
accompanied by the largest number of differences. 

III. The classification should be gradual, proceeding 
by a series of divisions and subdivisions. When the 
group to be classified consists of an enormous number 
of species, as in the case of animals and plants, the 
necessity of observing this rule is obvious. To descend 
at once from the Primary Divisions to, say. Genera and 
Species, would render the Classification comparatively 
worthless. The object of a classification being to bring 
together those groups which resemble each other and 
to separate those groups which differ from each other, 
we must take account of degrees of resemblance and 
difference, so that, as a rule, the number of gradations 
will increase with the number of groups to be classified. 
Both in Botany and Zoology, the grand divisions which 
seem now to be universally recognised are Primary 
Divisions, or Sub-Kingdoms (embranchements), Classes, 
Orders, Genera, and Species. Between these various 



CLA SSIFICA TJON. 6g 

Other divisions are interpolated, according to the seeming 
requirements of each particular system, and often accord- 
ing to the views of each individual author. Moreover, 
below Species are often reckoned Varieties, and even 
Varieties are sometimes subdivided, this being especially 
the case when animals have become domesticated or 
plants cultivated. Taking as an instance the Anthyllis 
Vulneraria (Common Lady's Finger), the divisions and 
subdivisions of a natural classification may be illustrated 
thus 22 :— 

I. Primary Division .... Cotyledones. 

i^II. Class ...... Dicotyledones. 

Subclass Calyciilorae. 

III. Order Leguminosae. 

Suborder Papilionaceae. 

Tribe Loteae. 

Subtribe ..... Genisteae. 

IV. Genus Anthyllis. 

Subgenus or Section . . . Vulneraria. 

V. Species Vulneraria. 

Variety Dillenii. 

Race ...... Floribus coccineis. 

Variation Foliis hirsutissimis. 

In very extensive groups, other divisions may be inter- 
polated ; thus a subgenus or section is often divided into 
a subsection. On the other hand, many of these divisions 
often disappear; if a genus consist of only a small 
number of species, and there be no very striking points 
of difference amongst them, we may descend at once, 

^ Balfour's Manual of Botany, § 725. 



70 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

without any intermediate divisions, from the Genus to 
its various Species. Sometimes, even, an order may 
contain only a single genus, or a genus a single species, 
in which case the two may be regarded as coextensive. 
In the case of Man, we saw that we descend at once from 
the Order to the varieties, the order Bimana being coex- 
tensive with the genus and species Homo, so that here 
three even of the grand divisions are coincident. 

IV. The groups should be so arranged, that those 
which have the closest affinities may be brought nearest 
to each other, while the distance of one group from 
another may be taken as a measure of its dissimil^ty 
from it. The observation of this rule would result in 
what Mr. Mill calls 'the arrangement of the natural 
groups into a natural series.' For the purposes of sub- 
sequent induction, it is plain that it is of the utmost 
importance not widely to dissever groups which present 
many phenomena in common, or which we even suspect 
may do so. The object aimed at by this rule is, to a 
great extent, attained by the observation of the Subor- 
dination of Characters (Rule 2), according to which, the 
higher the place of the division in the series, the more 
important is the collection of characters which serves for 
its basis. If Rule 2 were duly observed, it would be 
impossible for any two widely dissimilar groups to be 
brought into juxtaposition in the lower divisions of the 
series. Thus, the ox and the frog, the primrose and the 
mushroom, would in any natural system be at consider- 
able distances from each other. But it is not sufficient 



CLA SSIFICA TION. 7 1 

to observe the rule of the Subordination of Characters. 
The arrangement of the cognate groups in each division 
should be such that at the head of the series may come 
those groups which are most like the groups of the 
preceding division, while at the bottom of the series may 
come those groups which are most like the groups of 
the subsequent division. Thus, suppose that we have 
Orders A, B, C, of which B resembles A more than C 
does, and that A is subdivided into the genera a d' d" 
y b" € ; B into the genera ni m" nop' p" ; C into the 
genera :xf od' ^^y\y\ z; (of which the genera represented 
by the earlier letters of the alphabet are more akin to 
each other than those represented by the later, and 
conversely) ; in our arrangement we ought to place c in 
juxtaposition with m' m'\ and / p" in juxtaposition with 
:xf od\ the remaining groups being arranged, as above, 
on the same principle. If such an arrangement could 
be effected, it is plain that those groups which pre- 
sented in the greatest intensity the principal phenomena 
of the class of objects under investigation would come 
first in the series, and that those which presented them 
in the least intensity would come last. In Zoology, for 
instance, those groups would come first which presented 
in the greatest intensity the principal phenomena of 
animal life, and in Botany those which presented in the 
greatest intensity the phenomena of vegetable life. It 
is, of course, seldom, in the arrangement of natural 
objects, that we are able to draw up an exact table of 
precedency amongst the groups of any division, but we 



7a PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

are often able to say that this or that group or collection 
of groups {a or o^ d' d") should rank first in the series, 
or that it should rank before some other group or collec- 
tion of groups. Thus, no zoologist would hesitate to 
assign to man (the Order Bimana) the highest place in 
any classification of Mammalia, while he would place next 
the Order Quadrumana, and in this Order he would select 
apes, and, amongst apes, the anthropoid apes, to be 
brought into closest juxtaposition with man. 

This rule is obviously of most diflficult application. It 
points out an ideal to be aimed at,* but one which is never 
likely to be perfectly realised. So many are the pro- 
perties to be taken into consideration in every natural 
object, that it is often impossible to say that this object 
is, on the whole, more like another than that. The 
groups of the higher divisions may often, those of the 
lower may sometimes, be tabulated in some order of 
precedency ; but there remains a large majority of cases 
to which the Rule is inapplicable, or in which, at least, it 
has not yet been successfully applied. This is especially 
the case in Botany, where, though, in respect of com- 
plexity of structure and perfection of organism, Vascular 
plants may be ranked above Cellular, and Dicotyledons 
above Monocotyledons, there are but few cases among 
the subdivisions, especially of Monocotyledons and 
Dicotyledons, where any order of precedency can be 
established. But, even if the rule were of universal 
application, and if we were perfectly acquainted with all 
the properties of bodies and their relative value, it would 



CLA SSIFICA TION. 7 3 

not follow that we could establish what Dr. Whewell, in 
his opposition to this doctrine of Classification by Series, 
calls * a mere linear progression in nature/ There might 
still be' many Orders, Genera, or Species, which, to use 
a familiar expression, we should be obliged to bracket, 
* It would surely be possible,' says Mr. Mill ^^, ' to arrange 
^places (for example) in the order of their distance from 
the North Pole, though there would be not merely a 
plurality, but a whole circle of places at every single 
gradation in the scale.' 

Remark I. A natural classification is supposed to be com- 
plete, when it has descended as low as species, — a species 
being regarded as a group consisting of individuals, all of 
which have descended from a common stock. Or, if the 
process be reversed, and the classification be an ascend- 
ing instead of a descending one, species are regarded as 
the starting-point of the naturalist, and it is supposed that 
the problem before him is to group them under higher 
divisions. But a species may, as we have seen, be divided 
into varieties, sub-varieties, &c. Now, in what consists the 
difference between the relation of a variety to a species 
and the relation of a species to a genus ? To this ques- 
tion a very large section of naturalists now maintain that 
no satisfactory answer can be given. If it be said that 
varieties of the same species may be developed in the 
course of time, but that species themselves must be 
regarded as distinct, it may be asked on what grounds 

« Bk. IV. ch. viii. § i. Note. 



74 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

this supposition rests. Diflferent varieties of the same 
species are certainly more like each other than diflferent 
species of the same genus, just as species of the same 
genus have more resemblance than genera of the same 
order, or members of any lower division than members of 
any higher division ; but, given a larger amount of time, 
is there more diflftculty in supposing a common stock for 
the diflferent species of a genus than for the diflferent 
varieties of a species? This is the question originated 
with so much ability by Mr. Darwin in his work on the 
Origin of Species, His own solution of the question is 
well known. * It will be seen,' he says ^, * that I look at 
the term species, as one arbitrarily given for the sake of 
convenience to a set of individuals closely resembling 
each other, and that it does not essentially diflfer from the 
term variety, which is given to less distinct and more 
fluctuating forms. The term variety, again, in com- 
parison with mere individual diflferences, is also applied 
arbitrarily, and for mere convenience' sake/ It does not 
fall within our province to discuss the question of the 
'Origin of Species,' but it is desirable that the student 
should be aware that the practice of naturalists in stopping 
at species, as if they were the 'infimae species ' of the old 
logicians below which divisions need not proceed, is far 
from being universally accepted. 

Remark 2. As our knowledge of the external world 
becomes enlarged, the number of natural groups, recog- 

^ Darwin's Origin of Species, ch. ii. 



CLASSIFICA TION. 75 

. nised by the classificatory sciences, is being continually 
increased. Botanists and zoologists (especially the former) 
are constantly discovering or recognising new varieties, 
frequently new species, and occasionally, even, new 
genera and orders. * The known species of plants,' says 
Dr. Whewell^^ 'were 10,000 at the time of Linnaeus, 
and are now [a. d. 1858] probably 60,000.' The 
increase in the number of recognised varieties, sub- 
varieties, &c., is even still more rapid. One common 
effect of these constant discoveries and recognitions is to 
bridge over what previously appeared to be gaps in 
nature, thus illustrating the fact that there are but few 
breaks in natural phenomena, that there pervades nature 
a Law of Continuity, according to which a group seldom 
occurs to which some other group may not be found very 
closely allied. So complete, sometimes, is this continuity, 
that it becomes very difficult to distinguish the groups by 
any fixed characters. Two species (say) are discri- 
minated, and then a third group is found which partakes 
of the character of each of the others. This is con- 
stituted a new species, and then a fourth group is found 
intermediate between this and the first, and so on. * It 
has been shown,' says Dr. Carpenter, as quoted by 
Mr. Grove ^, *that a very wide range of variation exists 
among Orbitolites, not merely as regards external form, 
but also as to plan of developement ; and not merely as 

» History ofSeierUifie Ideas, Bk. VIII. ch. ii. § 6. 
^ Essay on Continuity, printed at the end of tiie Fifth Edition of 
The Correlation of Physical Forces, pp. 326, 327. 



j6 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION, 

to the shape and aspect of the entire organism, but also 
with respect to the size and configuration of its com- 
ponent parts. It would have been easy, by selecting 
only the most divergent types from amongst the whole 
series of specimens which I have examined, to prefer an 
apparently substantial claim on behalf of these to be 
accounted as so many distinct species. But after having 
classified the specimens which could be arranged around 
these types, a large proportion would yet have remained, 
either presenting chalracters intermediate between those of 
two or more of them, or actually combining those cha- 
racters in different parts of their fabric; thus showing 
that no lines of demarcation can be drawn across any 
part of the series that shall definitely separate it into any 
number of groups, each characterised by features entirely 
peculiar to itself.' We certainly find in nature a per- 
sistency of type, which is the result of the laws of here- 
ditary transmission; if there were no such persistency, 
the attempt to group natural objects would be fruitless 
and absurd. But, at the same time, when we have 
established groups, we constantly find that there are 
individual members diverging more or less from the 
ordinary type, and forming intermediate links between 
proximate classes. To adopt and alter a metaphor em- 
ployed by Dr. Whewell, natural classes may be regarded 
as the forests of neighbouring hills, the hills being seldom 
separated by well-defined valleys, and the valleys being 
frequently interspersed with straggling trees or clumps. 
Remark 3. It sometimes happens that one of the 



CLA S Sine A TION. J 7 

characters by which classes or groups are distinguished 
from each other is to be found, not invariably, but only 
usually or occasionally in the members of the group. 
Thus, in the description of the Order Rosaceae, we find 
that * the seeds are erect or inverted, usually exalbuminous 
Flowers sometimes imisexual/ Such in- 
definite descriptions would be entirely out of place in an 
artificial classification, but in a natural classification, where 
the entire assemblage of the characters must be taken 
into consideration, a character, though not found in- 
variably, or even though found but seldom, may still be 
valuable in distinguishing a group. 

Remark 4. The most important characters are not 
always those by which a group is most easily recognised. 
For the purpose of recognition, some external and pro- 
minent character or set of characters is generally best 
adapted. Thus, if we wished to determine whether a 
plant were monocotyledonous or dicotyledonous, our 
easiest course would be to examine the stem ; if the stem 
were endogenous, we should know that the plant was 
a monocotyledon, if exogenous, that the plant was a 
dicotyledon. A single character is often sufiicient to 
determine the place of a plant or animal in a series, 
because we already know that the possession of this 
character is a sign of the possession of the various other 
characters which are enumerated in the description of the 
natural class. The method of determining, by means of 
one or a few characters, the place of a natural object in a 
classification, is often called Diagnosis or Characteristick. 



78 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. . 

* The Characteristick/ says Dr. Whewell ^, * is an Arti- 
ficial Key to a Natural System. As being Artificial, it 
takes as few characters as possible ; as being Natural, its 
characters are not selected by any general or prescribed 
rule, but follow the natural affinities/ *The genera 
Lamium and Galeopsis (Dead Nettle and Hemp Nettle) 
are each formed into a separate group in virtue of their 
general resemblances and differences, and not because 
the former has one tooth on each side of the lower lip, 
and the latter a notch in its upper lip, though they are 
distinguished by these marks/ 



Note, — Dr. Whewell maintains that natural classes are 
determined, not by definition, that is, by an enumeration 
of characters, but by type, that is, by resemblance, more 
or less complete, to some one member of the class, round 
which the others are grouped. Thus, according to this 
theory, the Class Mammalia would be determined, not by 
an enumeration of characters, but by resemblance, more 
or less complete, to some typical specimen, say Dog ; the 
genus Dog would be determined not by an enumeration 
of the characters which are common to the dog, wolf, and 
fox (the species comprised in the genus), but by approxi- 
mation to the type-species dog ; similarly, the Order Ro- 
sacese would be determined not by an enumeration of 
characters, common to a large number of genera, but by 
the resemblance, more or less complete, of these genera 

^ History of Scientific Ideas, Bk. VIII. ch. ii. § 7. 



CLASSIFICATION. 79 

to the type-genus Rosa. Dr. Whewell's view will be un- 
derstood from the following extract : — 

*In a Natural Group the class is steadily 

fixed, though not precisely limited; it is given, though 
not circumscribed ; it is determined, not by a boundary 
line without, but by a central point within ; not by what 
it strictiy excludes, but by what it eminently includes ; by 
an example, not by a precept; in short, instead of 
Definition we have a Type for our director. 

'A Type is an example of any class, for instance, a 
species of a genus, which is considered as eminently pos- 
sessing the characters of the class. All the species which 
have a greater afiinity with this Type-species than with 
any others, form the genus, and are ranged about it, 
deviating from it in various directions and different de- 
grees. Thus a genus may consist of several species, 
which approach very near the type, and of which the 
claim to a place with it is obvious ; while there may be 
other i^ecies which straggle further from this central 
knot, and which yet are clearly more connected with it 
than with any other. And even if there should be some 
species of which the place is dubious, and which appear 
to be equally bound by two generic types, it is easily seen 
that this would not destroy the reality of the generic 
groups, any more than the scattered trees of the inter- 
vening plain prevent our speaking intelligibly of the distinct 
forests of two separate hills. 

*The Type-species of every genus, the Type-genus 
of every family, is, then, one which possesses all the 



8o PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

characters and properties of the genus in a marked and 
prominent manner. The Type of the Rose family has 
alternate stipulate leaves, wants the albumen, has the 
ovules not erect, has the stigmata simple, and besides 
these features, which distinguish it from the exceptions 
or varieties of its class, it has the features which make it 
prominent in its class. It is one of those which possess 
clearly several leading attributes; and thus, though we 
cannot say of any one genus that it mmi be the Type of 
the family, or of any one species that it must be the Type 
of the genus, we are still not wholly to seek : the Type 
must be connected by many afl&nities with most of the 
others of its group; it must be near the centre of the 
crowd, and not one of the stragglers ^J 

There is much force in what Dr. Whewell here says, 
but his main position appears to me to be incorrect. 
May not the various steps in the process of Classification 
be described as follows? We, first, observe a general 
resemblance amongst a variety of groups. Prompted by 
the observation of this resemblance, we determine to con- 
stitute the groups into a distinct class. But it is not 

^* History of Scientific Ideas, Bk. VIII. ch. ii. § 3. art. lo. Mr. Mill 
{Logic, Bk. IV. ch. vii. § 3, 4) examines Dr. Whewell's views at consider- 
able length. He appears to me, in this examination, to insist too em- 
phatically on what he calls * distinctions of kind,' and to assert, without 
sufhcient warrant, that * the species of Plants are not only real kinds, but 
are probably, all of them, real lowest kinds, Infimae Species, which if we 
were to subdivide into sub-classes, the subdivision would necessarily be 
founded on definite distinctions, not pointing (apart from what may be 
known of their causes or effects) to any difference beyond themselves.' 



NOMENCLATURE. 8 1 

sufficient simply to enumerate the groups which the class 
contains ; it is incumbent upon us to state the principle 
on which the classification was mjide. This statement 
consists in an enumeration of those characters which are 
common to all the members of the newly-constituted 
class, and which, at the same time, distinguish them from 
the members of other classes, with the addition, in some 
cases, of certain characters which belong to most, or, 
even, to a few only, of the members of the class. Thus, 
the class is determined (or ^ given* to use Dr. WhewelFs 
expression) by an enmneration of characters. But, when 
the class is once familiar to us, the repetition of the class- 
name suggests, not the characters, but some typical 
specimen of the class, some one group which stands out 
prominently as possessing the characters by which the 
class was determined, and it is by reference to this central 
specimen, as it were, that we fix the position of the other 
groups and adjudicate on the claims of any newly-dis- 
covered group to take its place by the side of the others. 
Thus, the t3T)e-species, type-genus, or typical order, may 
be of the greatest service as a convenient embodiment of 
the characters, but the characters must be enumerated, 
and the class determined, before we can select our typical 
example. 

(2) Op Nomenclature. 

Nomenclature is intimately connected with Classifica- 
tion. The groups, whether natural or artificial, into which 
objects are distributed, could neither be recollected by 

o 



82 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

ourselves nor communicated to others, unless they were 
fixed by the imposition of names. A Nomenclature is 
a collection of such names, applied to the members of 
the various divisions and subdivisions which constitute 
a classification. The number of natural groups, however, 
is so enormously large, that it would be next to im- 
possible to devise, and, if possible to devise, it would 
be impossible to remember, distinct names for each 
group. Thus, the known species of plants, for instance, 
amount to upwards of 60,000, and, if we took into 
account varieties, sub-varieties, &c., the number of groups 
would be represented by many multiples of this sum. 
Some artifice, therefore, is necessary by which a com- 
paratively small number of names may be made to dis- 
tinguish a large number of groups. Botany and Chemistry 
furnish admirable examples of the employment of such 
an artifice, and some knowledge of the principles which 
guide the imposition of names in those two sciences 
(a knowledge which may be easily acquired) would 
probably be of more service to the student than anything 
which he might learn from a body of rules for Nomen- 
clature in general. 

In Botany, the higher groups (including genera) have dis- 
tinct names. Thus, we have Dicotyledones, Rosaceae, Rosa, 
&c. But, when we arrive at the species, these are known 
by the generic name with the addition of some distinctive 
attribute. Thus, the genus Geranium is represented in 
the British Isles by thirteen species, called respectively 
Geranium phaeum, G. nodosum, G. sylvaticum, G. pratense, 



NOMENCLATURE. 83 

G. sanguineum, G. pyrenaicum, . G. pusillum, G. dis- 
sectum, G. columbinum, G. rotundifolium, G. molle, G. 
lucidum, G. robertianum. The specific names are se- 
lected from various considerations ; sometimes in honour 
of an individual (as Equisetum Mackaii, Rosa Wilsoni), 
sometimes from the country or the district in which the 
plant abounds, sometimes from the soil which is most 
favourable to it, sometimes from some peculiarity in the 
plant itself. So arbitrary and fanciful sometimes are these 
names, that Linnaeus (as we are told by Dr. Whewell^) 
* gave the name of Bauhinia to a plant with leaves in 
pairs, because the Bauhins were a pair of brothers, that 
of Banisteria to a climbing plant, in honour of Banister, 
who travelled among mountains.' It is plain that a name 
which describes some peculiarity in the plant itself is 
of most service to the learner ; but any name, easily re- 
membered, serves the main purpose of a nomenclature, 
which is to distinguish one group from another. Varieties, 
sub-varieties, &c., are distinguished from each other on 
the same principle as species. Thus, as we have seen, 
of the species Anthyllis Vulneraria there is a variety 
Dillenii, and of the variety Anthyllis Vulneraria Dillenii 
there is a * race' Floribus coccineis, and of the race there 
is a * variation' Foliis hirsutissimis. The nomenclature 
of Zoology is now generally constructed on the same 
principle as that of Botany. In some systems of Miner- 
alogy, three names are employed, nam^y, those of the 

» JKs/oiy of Scientific Ideas, Bk. VIII. ch. ii. § 6. 

O 2 



84 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

Order, Genus, and Species, as for instance, Rhombohe- 
dral Calc Haloide. 

The nomenclature of Chemistry, or, at least, of In- 
organic Chemistry, which, in some respects, furnishes 
an interesting example of a scientific nomenclature, is 
constructed on the principle of making the prefixes and 
affixes of the words employed significant of the nature 
of the substances for which they stand. Thus, we 
have the afiixes ide^ ic, otis, ate, ite, &c., and the pre- 
fixes mono, di, tri, sesqui\ &c., each having a special sig- 
nificance, though not always, unfortunately, an unam- 
biguous one. 

It would transcend the limits of this work to give an 
account, sufficiently clear and precise, of the Nomenclature 
of Inorganic Chemistry (which, moreover, is at present 
in a transitional state), but the student who is anxious 
to gain some idea of the principles on which it is con- 
structed, can refer to Watts' Dictionary of Chemistry, 
vol. iv. Art. Nomenclature. 



(3) Of Terminology. 

A Nomenclature of a Science is, as we have seen, a 
collection of names of groups. A Terminology is a col- 
lection of the names (or terms) which distinguish either 
the properties or the parts of the individual objects which 
the science re(?bgnises. Thus, when we speak of the 
genus *Rosa,' we are employing the nomenclature of 
Botany; but, when we say that the individuals of the 



TERMINOLOGY. 85 

genus * Rosa ' have ' their corolla imbricated before flower- 
ing, their styles with lateral insertion, their carpels nu- 
merous,' &c., we are employing not the nomenclature, 
but the terminology, of the science. In Botany we have 
an almost perfect example of a complete and judiciously 
constructed terminology. 

* The formation of an exact and extensive descriptive 
language for botany,' says Dr. WhewelP^, *has been 
executed with a degree of skill and felicity, which, before 
it was attained, could hardly have been dreamt of as 
attainable. Every part of a plant has been named ; and 
the form of every part, even the most minute, has had 
a large assemblage of descriptive terms appropriated to it, 
by means of which the botanist can convey and receive 
knowledge of form and structure, as exacdy as if each 
minute part were presented to him vastly magnified. This 
acquisition was part of the Linnaean Reform. "Toume- 
fort," says Decandolle, "appears to have been the first 
who really perceived the utility of fixing the sense of terms 
in such a way as always to employ the same word in the 
same sense, and always to express the same idea by the 
same word ; but it was Linnaeus who relfly created and 
fixed this botanical language, and this is his fairest claim 
to glory, for by this fixation of language he has shed 
clearness and precision over all parts of the science." 

* It is not necessary here to give any detailed account 
of the terms of botany. The fundamental ones have 
been gradually introduced, as the parts of plants were 

* History of Scientific Ideas, Bk. VIII. ch. ii. § 2. 



86 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

more carefully and minutely examined. Thus the flower 
was successively distinguished into the calyx, the corolla, 
the stamens, and the pistils : the sections of the corolla 
were termed petals by Columna ; those of the calyx were 
called sepals by Necker. Sometimes terms of greater 
generality were devised; 2& perianth to include the calyx 
and corolla, whether one or both of these were present ; 
pericarp for the part inclosing the grain, of whatever kind 
it be, fruit, nut, pod, &c. And it may easily be imagined 
that descriptive terms may, by definition and combination, 
become very numerous and distinct. Thus leaves may 
be called pinnatifid, pinnatipartite, pinnaiisect, pinnatilobate, 
palmatifid, palmatipartite, &c., and each of these words 
designates different combinations of the modes and extent 
of the divisions of the leaf with the divisions of its outline. 
In some cases arbitrary numerical relations are introduced 
into the definition : thus a leaf is called bilobate when it 
is divided into two parts by a notch ; but if the notch go 
to the middle of its length, it is bifid; if it go near the 
base of the leaf, it is bipartite ; if to the base, it is bisect. 
Thus, too, a pod of a cruciferous plant is a siliqua if it be 
four times as Iftig as it is broad, but if it be shorter than 
this it is a silicula. Such terms being established, the 
form of the very complex leaf or frond of a fern is exactly 
conveyed by the following phrase : " fronds rigid pinnate, 
pinnae recurved subunilateral pinnatifid, the segments 
linear undivided or bifid spinuloso-serrate." ' 

A Terminology, we have said, comprises the terms 
appropriated to express, not only the parts of objects, but 



TERMINOLOGY, 87 

also their properties. Thus, in the foregoing example, 
the words * sepals,' 'petals/ &c., express parts of the 
plant, the words * pinnatifid,' * bilobate,' &c., which are 
applied to the shape of the leaves, express properties. 
A complete terminology must be so constructed as to 
express every shade of diflference in all those properties 
which are recognised in a scientific treatment of the object. 
Thus, if colour be regarded as of importance in the de- 
scription of a plant, mineral, &c., it is essential that there 
shall be some appropriate term by which to describe every 
shade of colour. But there are few terms which, from 
their mere signification, can call up any precise idea in 
the mind. Hence it is necessary to fix by convention the 
precise meaning of every technical term employed in 
science. Again, to appropriate the words of Dr. Whewell, 
* The meaning of technical terms can be fixed in the first 
instance only by convention, and can be made intelligible 
only by presenting to the senses that which the terms are 
to signify. The knowledge of a colour by its name can 
only be taught through the eye. No description can con- 
vey to a hearer what we mean by apple-green or French 
grey. It might, perhaps, be supposed that, in the first 
example, the term apple, referring to so familiar an object, 
sufficiently suggests the colour intended. But it may 
easily be seen that this is not true; for apples are of 
many different hues of green, and it is only by a conven- 
tional selection that we can appropriate the term to one 
special shade. When this appropriation is once made, 
the term refers to the sensation, and not to the parts of 



88 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

this term ; for these enter into the compound merely as 
a help to the memory, whether the suggestion be a natural 
connection as in "apple-green," or a casual one as in 
" French grey." In order to derive due advantage from 
technical terms of this kind, they must be associated im- 
mediately with the perception to which they belong ; and 
not connected with it through the vague usages of common 
language. The memory must retain the sensation ; and 
the technical word must be understood as directly as- the 
most familiar word, and more distinctly. When we find 
such terms as tin-white or pinchbeck-brown, the metallic 
colour so denoted ought to start up in our memory with- 
out delay or search '^' When we have fixed, by conven- 
tion, the meaning of a term, it must invariably be em- 
ployed in this sense, and in no other. The least vague- 
ness or inconsistency in the use of terms may interpose 
a fatal obstacle in the way, not only of the learners, but 
even of the promoters of a science. The progress of the 
Mechanical Sciences and of what are commonly called 
Physics was long retarded by the vague and unintelligent 
use of such words as ' heavy,' * light,' * hot,' * cold,' * moist,' 
' dry,' &c. Even still such words as * force,' ' fluid,' 
* attraction,' * ether,' &c., are often employed without 
sufficient precision. 

A Terminology, as remarked by Dr. Whewell '*, is in- 
dispensably requisite in giving fixity to a Nomenclature. 
Thus, in Botany, * the recognition of the kinds of plants 

'* History of Scientific Ideas^ Bk. VIII. ch. ii. § 2. 
•^ Novum Organon RenovcUunif Bk. IV. Aphorism ii. 



HYPOTHESIS. 89 

must depend upon the exact comparison of their resem- 
blances and diflferences; and to become a part of per- 
manent science, this comparison must be recorded in 
words/ 

Dr. Whewell devotes the last Book of his Novum Or- 
ganon Renovatum to a series of aphorisms on the * Lan- 
guage of Science,' including both Nomenclature and 
Terminology. These aphorisms afford one of the best 
examples of Dr. Whewell's style and mode of treatment, 
and will well repay the attention of the student who is 
desirous of acquainting himself further with the methods 
of the Classificatory Sciences. Mr. Mill has some chapters 
{LogtCy Bk. IV. ch. iii-vi) on * Naming ' and the * Requisites 
of a Philosophical Language,' and, in addition to the pas- 
sage already referred to. Dr. Whewell treats these subjects 
in his History of Scientific Ideas, Bk. I. ch. ii ; Bk. VIIL 
ch. ii. §§ 2 and 6 ; Bk. VIIL ch. iii. art. 5. 

§ 3. On Hypothesis. 

When the mind has before it a number of observed 
facts, it is almost irresistibly driven to frame for itself 
some theory as to the mode of their co-existence or 
succession. It is from this irresistible impulse to refer to 
some law the various phenomena around us that all 
science as well as all scientific error has sprung. In all 
the more important branches of inquiry, true theories 
have usually been preceded by a number of false ones, 
and it has not tmfrequently occurred that the false theories 



90 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

have been mainly instrumental in conducting to the true. 
Thus, the elliptical theory of planetary motion was pre- 
ceded by the circular theory, with its various modifica- 
tions, and thfe undulatory theory of light by the emission 
theory. Rather than rest satisfied with a number of un- 
connected facts, men have often imagined the most 
absurd relations between phenomena, such as that a 
comet was the harbinger of war, or that the future could 
be foretold by birds. These theories, assumptions, or 
suppositions, when employed in scientific inquiry, are 
called hypotheses, and have already been alluded to 
(Chapter I. Appended Note 6). The word * hypothesis,* 
as commonly employed, is exclusive of propositions which 
rest upon absolute proof, whether inductive or deductive, 
and is generally used in contradistinction to them. Thus, 
we speak of a science being only in a hypothetical stage, 
or of a hypothesis being converted into an induction or 
being brought deductively under some general law already 
ascertained to be true. On the other hand, we should 
hardly dignify with the name of 'hypothesis' a supposition 
which, at least in the eyes of its framer, did not possess 
some amount of plausibility. A hypothesis ^' may be de- 
scribed as a supposition made without evidence or without 
sufficient evidence, in order that we may deduce from it 
conclusions agreeing with actual facts. If these conclusions 
are correctly deduced, and really agree with the facts, a 
presumption arises that the hypothesis is true. More- 

^ The following sentences, to the end of the paragraph, are slightly 
altered from Mr. Mill's Logic, Bk. III. ch. xiv. § 4. 



HYPOTHESIS. 91 

over, if the hypothesis relates to the cause, or mode of 
production of a phenomenon, it will serve, if admitted, 
to explain such facts as are found capable of being de- 
duced from it And this explanation is the purpose of 
many, if not most, hypotheses. Explanation, in the 
scientific sense, means the reduction of a series of facts 
which occur uniformly but are not connected by any 
known law of causation into a series which is so con- 
nected, or the reduction of complex laws of causation 
into simpler laws. If no such laws of causation are 
known to exist, we may suppose or imagine a law that 
would fulfil the requirement ; and this supposed law would 
be a hypothesis. 

A hypothesis may be serviceable in many ways. In 
the first place, it may afford a solution, more or less 
probable, of a problem which is incapable of any definite 
solution, or which, at least, has not yet been definitely 
solved. Thus, many of the advocates of the Darwinian 
hypothesis maintain that it is the most probable solution 
of an insoluble problem. Secondly, what was at first 
started as a hypothesis may ultimately be established by 
positive proof, as has been the case with the elliptical 
theory of planetary motion, and, as many suppose, with 
the undulatory theory of light. Thirdly, even though 
a hypothesis may ultimately be discovered to be false, it 
may be of great service in pointing the way to a truer 
theory. Thus, as already remarked, the circular theory of 
planetary motion, and the supplementary theory of epi- 
cycles and eccentrics, imdoubtedly contributed to the for- 



92 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

mation of the hypothesis which was eventually proved to 
be trae. Kepler himself tried no less than nineteen dif- 
ferent hypotheses, before he hit upon the right one, and 
his ultimate success was, no doubt, in no slight degree 
due to his unsuccessful eflforts. There is hardly any 
branch of science in which it might not be affirmed 
that, without a number of false guesses, true theories 
could never have been attained. Lastly, a hypothesis, 
whether true or false, if it be applicable to all the 
known facts, serves as a means of binding those facts 
together, of colligating them, to use a technical phrase, 
and thus, by presenting them under one point of 
view, plainly marks off the phenomena to be explained. 
A theory, Uke the Phlogistic theory in Chemistry, or 
the theory of epicycles and eccentrics (which, by being 
sufficiently extended, might have been made to include 
all the phenomena of planetary motion), may thus have 
been of the greatest service in the history of science, 
simply by keeping before mens minds the precise phe- 
nomena which demanded an explanation. 

The formation of hypotheses is obviously the work of 
the imaginative faculty, a faculty of hardly less importance 
in science than in art. To lay down rules for the ex- 
ercise of this faculty has hitherto been found futile. The 
object of Inductive Logic is rather to restrain the ex- 
uberant, than to excite the sluggish, imagination. The 
latter office is best fulfilled by recounting the great 
achievements of science, and thus arousing the ambition 
and kindling the enthusiasm of her votaries. The former 



RTPOTHESIS. 93 

(which is no less necessary) may be promoted by de- 
termining the conditions to which a hypothesis must con- . 
form, in order that it may rank as a provisional explana- 
tion of facts, and before it is entitled to demand the 
honom's of a rigorous inductive examination. These 
conditions may be reduced to three : — 

I. The hypothesis must not be known or suspected to 
be untrue. It would be absurd, for instance, in the pre- 
sent state of knowledge, to propose design or compact 
as the cause of the divergencies of the various dialects of 
a language, or to suppose the heavenly bodies to move in 
perfect circles. So simple a rule as this may appear to 
be superfluous, but it seems necessary to include it in the 
conditions to which a hypothesis must conform, as, other- 
wise, a perverted ingenuity might succeed in framing 
numberless hypotheses which violated none of the pre- 
liminary conditions. 

II. The hypothesis must be of such a character as to 
admit of verification or disproof, or at least of being 
rendered more or less probable, by subsequent investiga- 
tions ^. Unless this restriction were placed on the for- 
mation of hypotheses, there would be no limit to the 

'* It may occur to the student that we have not provided for the case 
where a supposition is already supported by a certain amount of probable 
evidence, but where it is not likely to be rendered more or less probable 
by further investigation. But such a supposition, though it would be an 
imperfect induction or deduction, could hardly be called a hypothesis, a 
term which seems always to imply something provisional, something 
which, on further inquiry, may be either confirmed or weakened, 
rendered more or less probable than it now is. 



94 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

wildness of conjecture in which theorists might indulge* 
. It might, for instance, be maintained that falling bodies 
are dragged to the earth by the action of invisible spirits, 
and, wild as such a theory would be, there is nothing 
positively to disprove it. Granted that, like many other 
products of imagination, such a theory might possibly 
be true, it would still fall without the scope of science. 
The aim of science is proof, present or prospective, and 
consequently what neither admits of proof, nor, so far 
as we can foresee, is ever likely to admit of it, or even 
approximate to it, is no fitting object of scientific in- 
quiry. As affording a caution against the unrestrained 
exercise of the imagination in matters of science, it may 
be useful to adduce a few instances of suppositions or 
hypotheses, which were probably considered as perfectly 
satisfactory by those who proposed them or amongst 
whom they were prevalent, which would now be regarded 
by all competent authorities as absurd, and which still do 
not admit of being distinctly disproved. 

It was once very generally held that the position 
of the planets with reference to the earth at any par- 
ticular moment determines not only the course of human 
events at that time, but the subsequent life of each 
person bom under the 'conjuncture.' Such an absurd 
theory is now probably held by no single person of sound 
understanding; but, so complicated is the web both of 
society and of individual life, and so easy would it be 
to explain 'apparent exceptions' by having recourse to 
* counteracting causes,' that, if any ingenious person were 



HYPOTHESIS. 95 

to maintain and defend this theory, it would probably 
be impossible to disprove it. Palmistry affords another 
instance of the same kind. The interlacing of the lines 
on the palms of the hands is said to indicate a man's 
* fortmies.' Such a notion is too absurd to be discussed ; 
but, if maintained, how could it be disproved ? It might 
always be said that the general theory of palmistry was 
true, though there might be some error in the particular 
rules by which the 'fortune'- in question was foretold**. 
The early history of Geology is full of hypotheses of 
this kind. The following examples of theories, which 
no scientific man would now entertain, but which hardly 
admit of disproof, are extracted from LyelFs Principles 
of Geology ^ .• — 

* Andrea Mattioll, an eminent botanist, the illustrator of 
Dioscorides, embraced the notion of Agricola, a skilful German 

^ The superstitions connected with dreams afford a similar instance : 
* The ancients were convinced that dreams were usually supernatural. 
If the dream was verified, this was plainly a prophecy. If the event was 
the exact opposite of what the dream foreshadowed, the latter was still 
Supernatural, for it was a recognised principle that dreams should some- 
times be interpreted by contraries. If the dream bore no relation to 
subsequent events unless it were transformed into a fantastic allegory, 
it was still supernatural, for allegory was one of the most ordinary forms 
of revelation. If no ingenuity of interpretation could find a prophetic 
meaning in a dream, its supernatural character was even then not 
necessarily destroyed, for Homer said there was a special portal through 
which deceptive visions passed into the mind, and the Fathers declared 
that it was one of the occupations of the daemons to perplex and be- 
wilder us with unmeaning dreams.' — Lecky's History of European 
Morals, vol. i. p. 385. 

* Lyeirs Principles of Geology, ch. iii. 



g6 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

miner, that a certain "materia pinguis," or "fatty matter,'* 
set into fermentation by heat, gave birth to fossil organic 
shapes. Yet Mattioli had come to the conclusion, from his 
own observations, that porous bodies, such as bones and shells, 
might be converted into stone, as being permeable to what 
he termed the " lapidifying juice." In like manner, Falloppio 
of Padua conceived that petrified shells were generated by 
fermentation in the spots where they are found, or that they 
had in some cases acquired their form from " the tumultuous 
movements of terrestrial exhalations." Although celebrated 
as a professor of anatomy, he taught that certain tusks of 
elephants, dug up in his time in Apulia, were mere earthy 
concretions ; and, consistently with these principles, he even 
went so far as to consider it probable, that the vases of Monte 
Testaceo at Rome were natural impressions stamped in the 
soil. In the same spirit, Mercati, who published, in 1574, 
faithful figures of the fossil shells preserved by Pope Sixtus V. 
in the Museum of the Vatican, expressed an opinion that they 
were mere stones, which had assumed their peculiar con- 
figuration from the influence of the heavenly bodies: and 
Olivi of Cremona, who described the fossil remains of a rich 
museum at Verona, was satisfied with considering them as 
mere "sports of nature." Some of the fanciful notions of 
those times were deemed less unreasonable, as being some- 
what in harmony with the Aristotelian theory of spontaneous 
generation, then taught in all the schools. For men who had 
been taught in early youth, that a large proportion of living 
animals and plants was formed from the fortuitous concourse 
of atoms, or had sprung from the corruption of organic matter, 
might easily persuade themselves, that organic shapes, often 
imperfectly preserved in the interior of solid rocks, owed their 
existence to causes equally obscure and mysterious.* 

* As to the nature of petrified shells, Quirini conceived that 
as earthy particles united in the sea to form the shells of mol- 
lusca, the same crystallizing process might be effected on the 



HYPOTHESIS. 97 

land ; and that, in the latter case^ the germs of the animals 
might have been disseminated through the substance of the 
rocks, and afterwards developed by virtue of humidity. 
Visionary as was this doctrine, it gained many proselytes even 
amongst the more sober reasoners of Italy and Germany ; for 
it conceded that the position of fossil bodies could not be 
accounted for by the diluvial theory.* 

It has been maintained by theologians, more ardent 
than discreet, that all fossils were the creations of the 
Devil, whose object was either to mimic the Almighty 
or to tempt mankind to disbelieve the Mosaic account 
of the creation. Such theories admit of no refutation; 
every argument, grounded on the resemblance of fossil 
remains to living organisms, shows only more distinctly, 
to those who have once embraced the idea, the success 
of the supposed agent as a mimic or as an impostor. 

Other instances of hypotheses which violate this rule are 
afforded by the Vortices of Descartes and the Crystalline 
Spheres of the ancient astronomers, both of which were 
imagined for the purpose of accounting for the pheno- 
mena of planetary motion. Both of these hypotheses 
have been subsequently disproved by the free passage of 
comets through the spaces supposed to be occupied, 
according to the one theory, by the Vortices, according 
to the other, by the soUd Crystalline Spheres. But at 
the time they were first started, there was no reasonable 
ground for supposing that, if untrue, they could be dis- 
proved, and, what is more important, there was no 
possibiUty of proving them or even rendering them 
more probable ; they were simply freaks of imagination, 

H 



98 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

incapable of proof and, to all appearance, of disproof. 
Another theory more absurd even than that of the solid 
crystalline spheres, but which has not, like that, been 
positively disproved, is the curious hypothesis by which 
Lodovico delle Colombe endeavoured to reconcile the 
Aristotelian doctrine that the moon was a perfect body 
with the recent discoveries of Galileo, who, by the aid 
of his telescope, had found that its surface was full of 
hollows, and was consequently charged by his enemies 
with taking a fiendish delight in distorting the fairest 
works of nature ; the apparently hollow parts, suggested 
Lodovico, were filled with a pure transparent crystal, and 
so both the astronomer and the Stagirite were right. 

It will be observed that we regard hypotheses as ad- 
missible, even though they are not likely ever to be 
positively proved or disproved, provided that the accumu- 
lation of further evidence is likely to render them more 
or less probable. Between such theories and the theories 
just exemplified, which are neither supported nor likely 
to be supported by any evidence whatever, there is the 
widest difference, and, while the one have no place in 
Science, the other, we conceive, have a legitimate claim 
to further consideration. The ideal of Science, it is true, 
is proof; but, while it can never recognise mere freaks 
of fancy, it is often compelled to rest content with pro- 
babilities. Instances of the hypotheses which we have 
in view are the Darwinian hypothesis and the Meteoric 
theory of the repair of Solar Heat, to be noticed pre- 
sently. 



HYPOTHESIS. 99 

III. The hypothesis must be applicable to the descrip- 
tion or explanation of all the observed phenomena, and, 
if it assign a cause, must assign a cause fully adequate 
to have produced them. A hypothesis, which does not 
satisfy this requirement, may be at once rejected. Thus, 
when the circular theory of planetary motion was found 
inapplicable to describe several of the phenomena, it 
was rightly abandoned, and the theory of epicycles and 
eccentrics, which, though erroneous, was fully adequate 
to explain all the known phenomena, was substituted for 
it. One of the most familiar instances of an inadequate 
hypothesis is the theory started by Voltaire, there is little 
doubt in irony, that the marine shells found on the tops 
of moimtains are Eastern species, dropped from the hats 
of pilgrims, as they returned from the Holy Land. Such 
a theory would obviously be inadequate to accoimt (i) for 
the numbers of the shells, (2) for the fact that they are 
found imbedded in the rocks, (3) for their existence far 
away from the tracks of pilgrims, to say nothing of the 
fact that many of these shells bear no resemblance to 
recent Eastern species, while none resemble them exactly. 
The contrast between an adequate and an inadequate 
hypothesis is well illustrated by two of the rival hypo- 
theses by which it is attempted to account for the genera- 
tion and the maintenance of solar heat. These are 
respectively the Meteoric Theory and the Theory of 
Chemical Combustion. In speaking of the former theory. 
Professor Tyndall says*'^ :— 

^ Heat a Mode of Motion, §§ 689-693. 

H 2 



lOO PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

* I have already alluded to another theory, which, however 
bold it may at first sight appear, deserves our serious atten- 
tion — the Meteoric Theory of the Sun. Kepler's celebrated 
statement that " there are more comets in the heavens than 
fish in the ocean," implies that a small portion only of the 
total number of comets belonging to our system are seen 
from the earth. But besides comets, and planets, and moons, 
a numerous class of bodies belong to our system which, from 
their smallness, might be regarded as cosmical atoms. Like 
the planets and the comets, these smaller asteroids obey the 
law of gravity, and revolve in elliptic orbits round the sun. 
It is they which, when they come within the earth's atmo- 
sphere, and are fired by friction, appear to us as meteors and 
falling stars. 

* On a bright night, twenty minutes rarely pass at any part 
of the earth's surface, without the appearance of at least one 
meteor. Twice a year (on the 12th of August and 14th of 
November) they appear in enormous numbers. During nine 
hours in Boston, when they were described as falling as thick 
as snowflakes, 240,000 meteors were observed. The number 
falling in a year might, perhaps, be estimated at hundreds or 
thousands of millions, and even these would constitute but 
a small portion of the total crowd of asteroids that circulate 
round the sun. From the phenomena of light and heat, and 
by direct observations on Encke's comet, we learn that the 
universe is filled by a resisting medium, through the friction 
of which all the masses of our system are drawn gradually 
towards the sun. And though the larger planets show, in 
historic times, no diminution of their periods of revolution, 
it may be otherwise with the smaller bodies. In the time 
required for the mean distance of the earth to alter a single 
yard, a small asteroid may have approached thousands of miles 
nearer to the sun. 

' Following up these reflections, we should be led to the 
conclusion, that while an immeasurable stream of ponderable 



HYPOTHESIS. lOI 

meteoric matter moves unceasingly towards the sun, it must 
augment in density as it approaches its centre of convergence. 
And here the conjecture naturally rises, whether that vast 
nebulous mass, the Zodiacal Light, which embraces the sun, 
may not be a crowd of meteors. It is at least proved that 
this luminous phenomenon arises from matter which circulates 
in obedience to planetary laws ; hence, the entire mass of the 
zodiacal light must be constantly approaching, and incessantly 
raining its substance down upon the sun. 

* It is easy to calculate both the maximum and the minimum 
velocity, imparted by the sun's attraction to an asteroid circu- 
lating round him. The maximum is generated when the body 
approaches the sun from an infinite distance; the entire pull 
of the sun being then exerted upon it. The minimum is that 
velocity which would barely enable the body to revolve round 
the sun close to his surface. The final velocity of the former, 
just before striking the sun, would be 390 miles a second, that 
of the latter 276 miles a second. The asteroid, on striking 
the sun, with the former velocity, would develope more than 
9000 times the heat generated by the combustion of an equal 
asteroid of solid coal; while the shock, in the latter case, 
would generate heat equal to that of the combustion of up- 
wards of 4000 such asteroids. It matters not, therefore, 
whether the substances falling into the sun be combustible or 
not ; their being combustible would not add sensibly to the 
tremendous heat produced by their mechanical collision. 

' Here, then, we have an agency competent to restore his 
lost energy to the sun, and to maintain a temperature at his 
surface which transcends all terrestrial combustion. In the 
fall of asteroids we find the means of producing the solar light 
and heat. It may be contended that this showering down of 
matter necessitates the growth of the sun ; it does so ; but 
the quantity necessary to maintain the observed calorific 
emission for 4000 years, would defeat the scrutiny of our best 
instruments. If the earth struck the sun, it would utterly 



I03 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

vanish from perception ; but the heat developed by its shock 
would cover the expenditure of a century.' 

Of the other theory, Professor Tyndall says'^ : — 

* Sir William Thomson adduces the following forcible 
considerations to show the inadequacy of chemical com- 
bination to produce the sun's heat. "Let us consider," he 
says, "how much chemical action would be required to 
produce the same effects. . . . Taking the former estimate, 
2781 thermal units ^ Centigrade (each 1390 foot pounds) 
or 3,869,000 foot pounds, which is equivalent to 7000 horse- 
power, as the rate per second of emission of energy from 
every square foot of the sun's surface, we find that more 
than 0.42 of a pound of coal per second, 1500 lbs. per hour, 
would be required to produce heat at the same rate. Now 
if all the fires of the whole Baltic fleet (this was written in 
1854) were heaped up and kept in full combustion over one 
or two square yards of surface, and if the surface of a globe 
all round had every square yard so occupied, where could 
a sufficient supply of air come from to sustain the com- 
bustion? Yet such is the condition we must suppose the 
sun to be in, according to the hypothesis now under con- 
sideration. ... If the products of combustion were gaseous, 
they would, in rising, check the necessary supplies of fresh 
air; if they were solid and liquid (as they might be if the 
fuel were metallic), they would interfere with the suj^ly of 
elements from below. In either, or in both ways, the fire 
would be choked, and I think it may be safely affirmed that 
no such fire could keep alight for more than a few minutes, 

*® Heat a Mode of Motion^ § 700. 

^ The thermal unit is the quantity of heat necessary to raise the 
temperature of a pound of water one degree. If the degree be centi- 
grade, this is equivalent to the heat generated by a pound weight falling 
from a height of 1390 feet against the earth. The term foot-pound 
expresses the energy requisite to lift one pound to the height of a foot. 



HYPOTHESIS. 103 

by any conceivable adaptation of air and fuel. If the sun 
be a burning mass it must be more analogous to burning 
gunpowder than to a fire burning in air; and it is quite 
conceivable that a solid mass, containing within itself all the 
elements required for combustion, provided the products of 
combustion are permanently gaseous, could bum oflf at its 
surface all round, and actually emit heat as copiously as the 
sun. Thus, an enormous globe of gun-cotton might, if at 
first cold, and once set on fire round its surface, get to a 
permanent rate of burning, in which any internal part would 
become heated sufficiently to ignite, only when nearly ap- 
proached by the burning surface. It is highly probable 
indeed that such a body might for a time be as large as the 
sun and give out luminous heat as copiously, to be freely 
radiated into space, without suflfering more absorption from 
its atmosphere of transparent gaseous products than the light 
of the sun actually does experience from the dense atmo- 
sphere through which it passes. Let us therefore consider 
at what rate such a body, giving out heat so copiously, would 
burn away ; the heat of combustion could probably not be so 
much as 4000 thermal units per pound of matter burned, the 
greatest thermal equivalent of chemical action yet ascertained 
falling considerably short of this. But 2781 thermal units 
(as found above) are emitted per second from each square 
foot of the sun; hence there would be a loss of about 0.7 
of a pound of matter per square foot per second ... or 
a layer half a foot thick in a minute, or 55 miles thick in 
a year. At the same rate continued, a mass as large as the 
sun is at present would burn away in 8000 years. If the sun 
has been burning at that rate in past time he must have been 
of double diameter, of quadruple heating power, and of eight- 
fold mass only 8000 years ago. We may therefore quite 
safely conclude that the sun does not get its heat by chemical 
action . . . and we must therefore look to the meteoric theory 
for fuel.* 



I04 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

A hypothesis which fulfils these three conditions is a 
legitimate hypothesis, though it must conform to still more 
rigorous requirements before it can be accepted as a 
complete Induction, or even be regarded as possessing 
any great amount of probability. Thus, the Meteoric 
Theory, though it is not yet proved, and perhaps never 
may be proved, to be the true explanation of the pheno- 
menon of solar heat, is perfectly tenable as a hypothesis. 
For, to state the conditions in the reverse order to that 
in which they have been enumerated above, the impact 
of a large number of meteors on a dense body, such as 
the sun probably is, would be competent or adequate to 
produce the given effect ; the theory in question is likely, 
if not to be proved or disproved, at least to be rendered 
more or less probable by the progress of astronomical 
science ; lastly, we do not know, nor have we any reason 
to suppose, that the hypothesis is an untrue explanation 
of the facts. But, though legitimate as a hypothesis, 
before we could accept the Meteoric Theory as a Valid 
or Complete Induction, we should require to know not 
only that there is a large number of meteors circulating 
round the sun, that these meteors have a tendency to fall 
into the central body, and that, i/thty fall or had fallen 
in sufficient quantities, they would be competent or would 
have been competent to produce the present amount of 
solar heat, but also that they do, as a matter of fact, fall 
in sufficient quantities to account for the phenomenon, 
or, at least, that nothing else but the showering down of 
asteroids and meteors could account for it. 



HYPOTHESIS. 105 

It was by availing himself of the latter mode of proof 
that Newton demonstrated the existence in the sun of a 
central force attracting the planets towards it. Assuming 
Kepler's hypothesis (then sufficiently verified by obser- 
vation to be universally accepted as a true statement 
of the facts), that equal areas are described by the 
radii vectores of the planets in equal times, Newton 
showed that this fact could be due to only one cause, 
namely, the deflection of the planets from their recti- 
linear course by a force acting in the direction of the 
sun's centre. The existence of the central force was, 
at first, started by him as a hypothesis. * He then proved 
that,' on the supposition of the existence of such a force, 
'the planet will describe, as we know by Kepler's first 
law that it does describe, equal areas in equal times ; and, 
lastly, he proved that if the force acted in any other di- 
rection whatever, the planet would not describe equal 
areas in equal times. It being thus shown that no other 
hypothesis would accord with the facts, the assumption 
was proved; the hypothesis became an inductive truth. 
Not only did Newton ascertain by this hypothetical pro- 
cess the direction of the deflecting force ; he proceeded 
in exactly the same manner to ascertain the law of varia- 
tion of the quantity of that force. He assumed that the 
force varied inversely as the square of the distance; 
showed that from this assumption the remaining two of 
Kepler's laws might be deduced; and finally, that any 
other law of variation would give results inconsistent with 
those laws, and inconsistent, therefore, with the real 



lo6 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

motions of the planets, of which Kepler's laws were 
known to be a correct expression *^/ 

It will be noticed that the course of demonstration pur- 
sued in this instance is the following : (i) we have certain 
observed facts ; (2) these observed facts are generalised 
in what are called Kepler's Laws; (3) we have the 
assimiption of the central force ; (4) it is shown that the 
central force will account for Kepler's Laws, and there- 
fore, of course, for the particular facts of observation on 
which those Laws were founded; (5) it is shown (and 
this is what properly constitutes the demonstration) 
that this assumption is the only one which will account 
for the Laws or the particular facts expressed by them ; 
(6) it is inferred inductively, by means of the Method 
of Difference (to be hereafter described), that the as- 
sumption of the central force, as it will account for, and 
is the only supposition which will account for, the ob- 
served facts, must be accepted as true ; (7) Kepler's 
Laws (which had hitherto been accepted as correct 
statements of observed facts, though they had not yet 
been explained by reference to any cause competent 
to account for them) are now proved deductively from 
what we have ascertained to be the Valid Induction of 
the Central Force. 

A Hypothesis can only be converted into a Valid 
Induction*^ by the application of one or other of the 

*" Mill's Logic, Bk. III. ch. xiv. § 4. 

" Though a hypothesis is usually contrasted with a Valid or Com- 
plete Induction, it must not be forgotten that we have admitted, as 



HYPOTHESIS, 107 

Inductive Methods (to be described in the next Chapter), 
or, if we insist on strict accurdcy of proof, of such of 
them as furnish absolutely certain conclusions. 



Note I. — According to the view here taken, which 
agrees with that of Mr. Mill, a hypothesis cannot claim 
to be regarded as an established truth, till it has con- 
formed to the requirements of one or other of the 
inductive methods, or has been shown to admit of 
being deduced from some previously established In- 
duction. Thus, when Newton proves the existence of 
a central force, deflecting the planets from the recti- 
lineal course which they would otherwise describe and 
making them describe curves round the sun, by show- 
ing that no other supposition would account for the fact 
that their radii vectores describe equal areas in equal times, 
he is, as Mr. Mill says, employing the Method of Difference. 
The demonstration ' affords the two instances, ABC, 
a be, and 'B C, he, A represents central force ; ABC, 
the planets plus a central force ; B C, the planets as they 
would be without a central force. The planets with a 
central force give a (areas proportional to the times) ; the 

legitimate, hypotheses which are never likely to rest on more than pro- 
bable evidence. These can, of course, receive accessions of proof only 
by the same means as those by which we establish Imperfect Inductions. 
It should also be remembered that the truth of a hypothesis may be 
demonstrated by deductive as well as by inductive methods. 



Io8 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

planets without a central force give 3 r (a set of motions) 
without a, or with something else instead of a. This is 
the Method of Difference in all its strictness. It is true, 
the two instances which the method requires are obtained 
in this case, not by experiment, but by a prior deduction. 
But that is of no consequence. It is immaterial what is 
the nature of the evidence from which we derive the as- 
surance that ABC will produce adc^ and B C only dc ; 
it is enough that we have that assurance. In the present 
case, a process of reasoning furnished Newton with the 
very instances, which, if the nature of the case had ad- 
mitted of it, he would have sought by experiment *^' 

Dr. Whewell, who does not acknowledge the utility of 
Mr. Mill's methods, appears to regard the inductive pro- 
cess as consisting simply in the framing of successive 
hypotheses, the comparison of these hypotheses with the 
ascertained facts of nature, and the introduction into 
them of such modifications as that comparison may 
render necessary. The first requisite in a hypothesis, 
according to Dr. Whewell, is that it shall explain all 
the observed facts. But its probability, he urges, will 
be considerably enhanced, if, in addition to explaining 
observed facts, it enables us to predict the future. 
' Thus the hypotheses which we accept ought to explain 
phenomena which we have observed. But they ought 
to do more than this : our hypotheses ought to foretel 
phenomena which have not yet been observed; at least 

*» MUl's Logic, Bk. III. ch. xiv. § 4. 



HYPOTHESIS. 109 

all phenomena of the same kind as those which the 
hypothesis was invented to explain. For our assent to 
the hypothesis implies that it is held to be true of all 
particular instances. That these cases belong to past or 
to future times, that they have or have not already oc- 
curred, makes no difference in the applicability of the 
rule to them. Because the rule prevails, it includes all 
cases ; and will determine them all, if we can only cal- 
culate its real consequences. Hence it will predict the 
results of new combinations, as well as explain the ap- 
pearances which have occurred in old ones. And that 
it does this with certainty and correctness, is one mode 
in which the hypothesis is to be verified as right and 
useful *'.' 

Curiously enough, the first hypothesis which Dr. 
Whewell cites as having fulfilled both these conditions, 
is also one which eventually proved to be false. *For 
example, the Epicyclical Theory of the heavens was 
confirmed by its predicting truly eclipses of the sun 
and moon, configurations of the planets, and other 
celestial phenomena; and by its leading to the con- 
struction of Tables by which the places of the heavenly 
bodies were given at every moment of time. The truth 
and accuracy of these predictions were a proof that the 
hypothesis was valuable, and, at least to a great extent, 
true; although, as was afterwards found, it involved a 
false representation of the structure of the heavens.' A 

^ Novum Organon Renovatumt Bk. II. cb. v. art. 10. 



no PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

theory may thus not only enable us to explain known 
facts, but even to predict the future, and still be untrae. 
Notwithstanding, however, the infelicitous character of the 
example, Dr. Whewell attaches the greatest importance 
to the fulfilment of this condition by a hypothesis. * Men 
cannot help believing that the laws laid down by dis- 
coverers must be in a great measure identical with the 
real laws of nature, when the discoverers thus determine 
effects beforehand in the same manner in which nature 
herself determines them when the occasion occurs. Those 
who can do this, must, to a considerable extent, have 
detected nature's secret ; — ^must have fixed upon the con- 
ditions to which she attends, and must have seized the 
rules by which she applies them. Such a coincidence of 
untried facts with speculative assertions cannot be the 
work of chance, but implies some large portion of truth 
in the principles on which the reasoning is founded. To 
trace order and law in that which has been observed, may 
be considered as interpreting what nature has written 
down for us, and will commonly prove that we under- 
stand her alphabet. But to predict what has not been 
observed, is to attempt ourselves to use the legislative 
phrases of nature; and when she responds plainly and 
precisely to that which we thus utter, we cannot but sup- 
pose that we have in a great measure made ourselves 
masters of the meaning and structure of her language. 
The prediction of results, even of the same kind as those 
which have been observed, in new cases, is a proof of real 
success in our inductive processes.' 



HYPOTHESIS. Ill 

But what appears to Dr. Whewell to establish the truth 
of a hypothesis beyond all question is what he calls a 
Consilience of Inductions. ' We have here spoken of the 
prediction of facts of the same kind as those from which 
our rule was collected. But the evidence in favour of our 
induction is of a much higher and more forcible character 
when it enables us to explain and determine cases of 
a kind different from those which were contemplated in 
the formation of our hypothesis. The instances in which 
this has occurred, indeed, impress us with a conviction 
that the truth of our hypothesis is certain. No accident 
could give rise to such an extraordinary coincidence. No 
false supposition could, after being adjusted to one class 
of phenomena, exactly represent a different class, where 
the agreement was unforeseen and uncontemplated. That 
rules springing from remote and unconnected quarters 
should thus leap to the same point, can only arise from 
that being the point where truth resides. 

* Accordingly the cases in which inductions from classes 
of facts altogether different have thus jumped together, 
belong only to the best established theories which the 
history of science contains. And as I shall have occasion 
to refer to this peculiar feature in their evidence, I will 
take the liberty of describing it by a particular phrase; 
and will term it the Consilience of Inductions, 

'It is exemplified principally in some of the greatest 
discoveries. Thus it was found by Newton that the 
doctrine of the Attraction of the Sun varying according 
to the Inverse Square of the distance, which explained 



112 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. 

Kepler's Third Law, of the proportionality of the cubes 
of the distances to the squares of the periodic times of 
the planets, explained also his First and Second Laws, 
of the elliptical motion of each planet ; although no con- 
nection of these laws had been visible before. Again, it 
appeared that the force of Universal Gravitation, which 
had been inferred from the Perturbations of the moon 
and planets by the sun and by each other, also accounted 
for the fact, apparently altogether dissimilar and remote, 
of the Precession of the equinoxes. Here was a most 
striking and surprising coincidence, which gave to the 
theory a stamp of truth beyond the power of ingenuity to 
counterfeit **/ 

It is undeniable that a theory which thus appears to 
afford an explanation of different classes of facts strikes 
the imagination with considerable force, and that its very 
simplicity furnishes primd facie evidence of its truth. 
But what is required before a hypothesis can be placed 
beyond suspicion is formal proof, and that, it appears 
to me, is furnished by Mr. Mill's 'methods,' and not 
by Dr. WhewelFs requisitions of explanation, prediction, 
and consilience of inductions. For the questions at issue 
between Mr. Mill and Dr. Whewell, see WhewelFs 
Novum Organon Renovatum (where his views are stated 
in their latest and most matured form), Bk. II. ch. v. 
§ 3, and Mill's Logic, Bk. III. ch. xiv. § 6. 

** Novum Organon Renovatum^ Bk. II. ch. v. art. 1 1 . 



HYPOTHESIS. 113 

Noie 2. — In attempting to determine the conditions to 
which a legitimate hypothesis must conform, I have avoided 
the employment of the expressions vera causa and adcB' 
quata causa. In the first place, a hypothesis may simply 
attempt to find a general expression for a number of 
isolated facts without referring them to any cause, as was 
the case with the various hypotheses respecting the shape 
of the planetary orbits, and hence to speak as if a 
hypothesis always assigned a cause is an undue limitation 
of the meaning of the word. But to the expression vera 
causa there is a more special exception. Its meaning is 
ambiguous. Is it the actual cause which produces a pheno- 
menon, or a cause which we know to be actually existent, 
or a cause analogous to an existent cause ? The student 
will find a criticism of this expression (first employed by 
Newton) in Dr. WhewelFs Philosophy of Discovery, ch. xviii. 
§ 5, &c. The expression cannot have been used in the first, 
which is its most obvious, sense, for, as Dr. Whewell says, 
* although it is the philosopher's aim to discover such 
causes, he would be little aided in his search of truth, by 
being told that it is truth which he is to seek.' But in the 
second of the two remaining senses, the requirement, as 
would now be generally acknowledged, is too stringent, 
and, if it had been invariably observed, would have pre- 
vented us from reaping some of the greatest discoveries 
in science, while in the last it is so vague as to be of no 
practical service. It has been attempted to aflix other 
meanings to the phrase; but there can be little doubt 
that Newton, having in mind the Vortices of Descartes, 



114 PROCESSES SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION, 

intended to protest against the introduction of causes of 
whose existence we have no direct knowledge, and con- 
sequently laid down a rule, which the subsequent history 
of science has shown to be needlessly stringent. 



Note 3. — We sometimes find the expression a * gratuitous 
hypothesis/ By this is meant the assumption of an 
unknown cause, when the phenomenon is capable of 
being explained by the operation of known causes, or 
the introduction of an^ extraneous (though it may be 
known) cause, when the phenomenon is capable of being 
accounted for by the causes already known to be in 
operation. Of the latter case we should have instances, 
where a man is supposed to have acted at the suggestion 
of another, though his own motives would supply a 
sufficient explanation of his conduct, or where a man 
is supposed to have been poisoned though he was already 
known to have been suffering from a fatal disease. Of 
the former case we should have instances in the crystalline 
spheres of the- ancient astronomers and in the masses 
of crystal which were supposed by Lodovico delle Colombe 
to fill up the cavities of the moon (there being no in- 
stances known to us of the existence of crystal in these 
huge masses, and the phenomena being capable of 
explanation without making the supposition); in the 
caloric (which was supposed to be a distinct substance) 
of the early writers on heat, and in the * electrical fluid' 
of the early electricians. In all these instances, under 



HYPOTHESIS. 115 

whichever of the two cases they may fall, the objection 
to the hypothesis is that it seems ' not to be needed/ 

I have said nothing of * gratuitous hypotheses ' in the 
text, as a h}'pothesis, though it may appear to be gra- 
tuitous, may still be legitimate, and may even ultimately 
turn out to be true. 



c*gg<-e5-< 



1 2 



CHAPTER III. 
On the Inductive Methods. 

INDUCTION has been defined to be a legitimate 
inference from the known to the imknown. But the 
unknown must not be entirely imknown. It must be 
known to agree in certain circumstances with the known, 
and it is in virtue of this agreement that the inference is 
made. Now, how are we to ascertain what are the com- 
mon circumstances which justify the inductive infer- 
ence. X and Y may both agree in exhibiting the circum- 
stances ay 3, r, but it will not follow because X exhibits 
the quality niy that therefore this quality will also neces- 
sarily be found in Y. Nor even, if twenty, thirty, a 
hundred, or a thousand cases could be adduced in which 
the circumstances a^ h, c were found to be accompanied 
by the circumstance m, would it follow necessarily (it 
might not even follow probably) that the next case in 
which we detected the circumstances a^bjC would also 
exhibit the quality m. We might pass through a field 
containing thousands of blue hyacinths, but this would 
not justify us in expecting that the next time we saw a 



INDUCTIVE METHODS. II7 

hyacinth, it would be a blue one. This form of induction 
(Indudio per Simplicem Enumerationem) may have no 
value whatever. In most cases, the condemnation passed 
on it by Bacon ^ is perfectly just: 'Inductio quae pro- 
cedit per enumerationem simplicem, res puerilis est, et 
precario concludit, et periculo exponitur ab instantia con- 
tradictoria, et plenimque secundum pauciora quam par 
est, et ex his tantummodo quae praesto sunt, pronunciat.' 
But if we have reason to think that any instances to the 
contrary, if there were such, would be known to us, the 
argument may possess considerable value, and if, as in 
the case of the Laws of Causation and of the Uniformity 
of Nature, we feel certain, from a wide and various ex- 
perience, that there are no cases to the contrary, no 
stronger argument (to us individually) can be adduced. 
It is rarely, however, that an Inductio per Simplicem 
Enumerationem can afford us this certainty ^. Our trust- 
worthy inductions are, in nearly all cases, the result of 
our detecting some fact of causation among the observed 
phenomena. We find, for instance, that, amongst the 
observed phenomena «, 3, r, d of X, a is the cause of r, 
and, consequently, if we observe the phenomenon a in Y, 
we infer that, if there are no counteracting circumstances, 
Y will possess the quality c as well ; or, if we observe 

* Novum Organunit Bk. I. aph. cv. 

^ It must be remembered that a complete enumeration of instances, 
when we know the enumeration to be complete, inasmuch as it leaves 
no room for an inference from the known to the unknown, does not 
furnish an inductive but a deductive argument. See Elements 0/ De- 
ductive Logic, Part III. ch. i. appended Note a. 



Il8 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

the phenomenon c in Y, we infer that it is not unlikely ' 
that a may be present as well. The problem of Indue- 
tion, therefore, resolves itself (except in the few very rare 
cases in which we may legitimately employ Inductio per 
Simplicem Enumerationem) into the problem of detecting 
facts of Causation. Certain rules for this purpose have 
been laid down by Mr. Mill, called by him the Experi- 
mental Methods, but which we shall distinguish as the 
Inductive Methods. 

Before proceeding to state and explain these Rules or 
Methods, it may be useful to make some preliminary 
remarks on the nature of the causal relations which may 
subsist among phenomena. 

(i) The same cause, unless there are counteracting 
circumstances, that is, other causes which prevent it from 
acting or which modify its action, is invariably followed 
by the same effect. 

(2) As already shown (Chapter I. pp. 10-12), several 
causes may have co-operated in producing any given 
effect In this case, it is not unusual to speak of the 
' combination of causes ' or the * sum of the causes.' 

(3) The same effect may be due to several distinct 
causes, or combinations of causes, being due sometimes 
to one and sometimes to another, and, hence, though we 
may always argue from a particular cause to its effect, we 
cannot always argue from an effect to any particular 

^ We say * not unlikely/ for c might be due to some other cause as 
well as a, and, therefore, the presence of c does not enable us to infer 
with certainty the presence of a, as that of a does the presence of c. 



INDUCTIVE METHODS. II9 

cause, Thus, ignition may be due, not only to the concen- 
tration of the rays of. solar heat, but also to friction, 
electricity, &c. 

(4) It frequently happens that between the original 
cause and the ultimate effect there intervene a number 
of intermediate causes. Thus, suppose we make an 
experiment by which motion is converted into heat, heat 
into electricity, and electricity into chemical affinity ; we 
might, roughly speaking, say that motion had been 
the cause of the chemical afl&nity, or chemical affinity 
the effect of the motion, but, speaking strictly, we ought 
to enumerate the intervening causes. 

(5) Sometimes a number of effects appear to be pro- 
duced simultaneously by the same cause. Thus, it would 
appear that there are many cases in which, if one of the 
agents, motion, heat, light, electricity, magnetism, and 
chemical action, is excited, the rest are simultaneously 
developed*. These simultaneous effects, whether we 
conceive that they are really or only apparently simul- 
taneous, would be called joint or common effects of. the 
cause. The expression * joint effects ' is also employed 
for the effects produced by the same cause on different 
bodies, or different portions of the same body. Thus, if 
a blow bruises my forehead, and at the same time gives 
me a headache, the bruise and the headache would be 
called joint effects of the blow. These joint effects may 
be, as it were, in different degrees of descent from the 
same cause. Thus, if the headache incapacitates me for 

* See Grove's Correlation of Physical Forces, Concluding Remarks. 



lao INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

work, my incapacity for work and the bruise on my fore- 
head would be joint effects, but in different degrees of 
descent from the original cause. 

Any phenomena which are cpnnected, either as cause 
and effect, and that either immediately or remotely, or as 
joint effects, and that either in the same or in different 
degrees of descent from the same cause, may be spoken 
of as being causally connected^ or as being related to one 
another through ^m&facl of causation. 

We now proceed to the statement of the Inductive 
Methods. 

METHOD OF AGREEMENT. 
CANON ^, 

If two or more instances of the phenomenon under investi- 
gation have only one circumstance in common^ the circum- 
stance in which alone all the instances agree may he regarded, 
with more or less of probability , as the cause (or effect) of the 
given phenomenon^ or, at least, as connected with it through 
some fact of causation. 

Wherever the phenomenon a is found, we observe that 
b is found, either invariably or frequently ^, in conjunction 

' The statement of the Canons is taken, with some modifications, 
from Mr. Mill's Logic. The authorities for the various examples, when 
these are not of a familiar character, are cited at the foot of the page. 

' We add * or frequently,* as it is not necessary that the conjunction 
shall be invariable. The student need not, however, at present trouble 
himself with the distinction, which will be fully explained below. See 
pp.128, 135-137- 



METHOIi OF AGREEMENT, 121 

with it. This fact leads us to suspect that there is some 
causal connection between them. On what grounds, 
and under what circumstances, are we justified in drawing 
such an inference ? And what is the particular character 
of the inference which we are justified in drawing? 
The answer to these questions involves many difiiculties, 
of which we shall now attempt to offer a solution. 

When antecedents and consequents are discriminated 
in this discussion, antecedents will be represented by 
Roman capitals, A, B, C, &c., and consequents by Greek 
characters, a, ft y, &c. When circumstances are not 
distinguished as antecedents and consequents, we shall 
employ the small Roman letters, a, b, c, &c. 

Now, suppose that we have A B followed by o 0, and 
A C by a y ; it might, at first sight, appear that A must be 
the cause of a, or, if we were attempting to ascertain the 
effect of a given cause (which, however, is a much rarer 
application of this method), that a must be the effect 
of A. And there is much plausibility in this supposition, 
for whatever can, in any given instance, be excluded, 
or, to use the technical term, eliminated without pre- 
judice to a phenomenon, cannot have any influence 
on it in the way of causation, nor can an effect which 
disappears be due to a cause which continues to 
operate. Thus, if we were attempting to find the 
cause of a given effect a, it might be argued that B 
cannot be its cause, for it is absent in one of the cases 
where a is present, and similarly of C ; but that a must be 
due to some cause; and, consequently, is due to A, the only 



122 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

antecedent remaining. Or, if we were attempting to find 
the effect of a given cause A, it might be argued that fi 
cannot be its effect, for it is absent in one of the cases 
where A is present, and similarly of y; but that, as a has 
been permanently present, A must be its cause. If it 
were not for the fact that the same event may be due to 
a great number of distinct causes (as is exemplified in the 
familiar cases of motion, death, disease, &c.), this reason- 
ing would be perfectly just. Now it will be observed that, 
when B was removed, it was replaced by C. It is, there- 
fore, conceivable that a may have been due to B in the 
first instance, and to C in the second, it being, of course, 
in each case, only a portion of the effect, the remaining 
portions being respectively /S, y, and A having been 
throughout inoperative. This consideration, it is plain, 
vitiates the reasoning, whether we are attempting to dis- 
cover the effect of a given cause or the cause of a given 
effect. Thus, suppose that there are two distinct drugs, 
either of which is potent to remove a given disease, and 
that, in administering each of them, we mix it with some 
perfectly inert substance, which is the same in each 
case ; if the principles of the above reasoning were cor- 
rect, and we were justified in neglecting to take account 
of what may be called the Plurality of Causes, we should 
be at liberty to argue (if we were seeking the cause of a 
given effect) that the restoration of the patients to health 
was, in each case, due to the inert substance, or (if we 
were seeking the effect of a given cause) that the inert 
substance was the cause of their restoration to health. 



METHOD OF AGREEMENT. 1 23 

But, if the Method of Agreement is open to so serious 
an objection, it may be asked on what grounds is it 
recognised as an Inductive Method? The answer is 
that, by the multiplication and variation of instances, the 
possible error due to the Plurality of Causes may be 
rendered less and less probable, till, at last, for all 
practical purposes, it may be regarded as having dis- 
appeared. Thus, if to the instances AB, ajS; AC, ay; 
we can add A D, ad; A E, ae, &c. &c. ; it is plain that we 
may, at each step, be very considerably diminishing the 
possibility of an error in our reasoning, and, after a certain 
number of instances, may be justified in feeling morally 
certain that we have avoided it. It is not likely that, 
in a number of instances, each agreeing in some one 
circumstance (besides the phenomenon which is being 
investigated) but differing as widely as possible in all 
other circumstances, the same event should in each case, 
or in a majority of cases, or in even a great number of 
cases, be due to different causes. The chance of an inert 
substance being successively mixed with two potent 
drugs, and of the effects which are really due to them 
being erroneously ascribed to it, is, in the present state 
of medical science, but a very slight one; but the pro- 
bability is obviously considerably diminished, if instead 
of two such errors we suppose three, instead of three 
we suppose four, and so on. 

For the sake of simplicity, we have assumed groups 
of two antecedents and two consequents (A B, ajS ; A C, 
ay ; &c. &c.), but it is extremely seldom that we find in 



124 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

nature combinations so simple. We have usually a vast 
mass of antecedents and a vast mass of consequents 
(or, to state the same proposition in more scientific 
language, a vast mass of antecedents all, or most of them, 
contributing to a complex efiect), and hence it often 
becomes a matter of extreme difficulty to discover a 
collection of instances which, presenting the phenomenon 
in question, agree in only one other circumstance or even 
in a small number of other circumstances. The dif- 
ficulty, therefore, of rigidly satisfying the requirements 
of the Method must be added to what Mr. Mill calls its 
characteristic imperfection^ namely, the imcertainty attach- 
ing to its conclusions from the consideration of the 
Plurality of Causes. 

But there is still a third difficulty incident to the 
Method of Agreement, which, however, is, in a majority 
of cases, of a theoretical rather than a practical nature. 
If we insisted literally on the fulfilment of the condition 
that the instances presenting the given phenomenon 
should have only one other circumstance in conunon, 
it would be simply impossible to find such instances. 
All instances must agree in a number of circumstances 
which are immaterial to the point under investigation. 
Thus, if we are enquiring into the properties of a group 
of external objects, they will all agree in the fact that they 
are subject to the action of gravity, and probably also 
in the facts that they are surrounded by atmospheric air 
and exposed to the light of the sun; but, if these facts 
do not affect the subject of our enquiry, we piay pass 



METHOD OF AGREEMENT. 12^ 

them over as if they had no existence. When, therefore, 
we employ the expression *only one circumstance in 
common,' we must be understood to mean 'only one 
material circumstance,' and to exclude all circumstances 
which a wide experience or previous inductions have 
shown to be immaterial to the question before us. It 
need hardly be added that, in forming this judgment 
as to the material or immaterial character of the circum- 
stances, the greatest caution is often required. 

But, suppose we have ascertained (when enquiring 
into the cause of a given effect) that the instances agree 
in only one antecedent (or rather one material ante- 
cedent), namely A, and that we have so multiplied and 
varied the instances as to have satisfied ourselves that 
we have excluded the possibility of a Plurality of 
Causes, are we justified in drawing the inference that 
A is the cause of a? We are so justified, for a must 
be due to something which went before it, and, as it 
has been shown that it is not due to any of the other 
antecedents, it must be due to A. Similarly, if our 
object be to enquire into the effect of a given cause A, 
we are justified, if we discover a consequent a, of which 
we can assure ourselves that it is not due to any of the 
other antecedents, in regarding it as the effect of A. 

Hitherto, we have supposed the antecedents and con- 
sequents to be discriminated. But, suppose that we have 
a number of phenomena abcde, adefg, &c., in which 
we cannot discriminate them, how will the conclusions 
of the Method of Agreement be affected? There will, 



126 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

as in the former cases, obviously be the difficulties arising 
from Plurality of Causes and the complexity of the 
phenomena. Supposing, however, these to be overcome, 
and two circumstances only, a and b, to have been ascer- 
tained to be common to all the instances, what conclusion 
shall we be justified in drawing with reference to the 
connection between a and b ? It is only reasonable 
to suppose that they must be causally connected in 
some way, else their connection would be a mere 
casual coincidence; a supposition which we assume to 
have been excluded by the number and variety of the 
instances examined. But they need not necessarily stand 
to each other in the relation of cause and effect, for they 
may be common effects (in the same, or in different 
degrees of descent) of some cause which has itself ceased 
to operate. In social and physiological phenomena this 
is frequently the case. A disease will leave effects behind 
it which will continue to co-exist for years after the 
disease has passed away, and which, though not standing 
to each other in the relation of cause and effect, are thus 
causally connected. The social condition of any old 
country is, to a great extent, an aggregate of such effects, 
the original cause or causes of which have long ceased 
to have any existence. 

It should be noticed that the Method of Agreement 
is mainly, though not exclusively, a Method of Observa- 
tion rather than of Experiment, and that it is applied far 
more frequently to enquire into the causes of given effects 
than into the effects of given causes. The reason of this 



METHOD OF AGREEMENT. 1 27 

peculiarity is that in trying an experiment, pr in enquiring 
into the effect of a given cause, we are generally able 
to employ one of the other Methods, which, as will be 
seen, are not exposed to the same diflSculties as the 
Method of Agreement. 

It should also be noticed that where, after a careful 
elimination and an examination of a sufficiently large 
number of instances, we have, instead of two, some three, 
four, or more circumstances common to all the instances, 
we may, with much probability, regard them all, unless 
we know or suspect any of them to be immaterial cir- 
cumstances, as being causally connected. If the common 
circumstances be a, b, c, d, this is all that we can infer. 
But, if they be A, B, C, a, we may infer that the cause 
of a is certainly either A or B or C, or some two of them 
acting jointly, or all acting together, while those common 
antecedents, which do not either constitute or contribute 
to the cause, probably stand in some causal relation to 
it, and consequently to its effect a. Similar conclusions 
may be drawn, if the common circumstances left after 
elimination be A, a, ft y. Thus, for instance, a, jS, y 
might all be joint effects of A, or a might be its im- 
mediate effect, and ft y effects of a, and so on. 

It is perhaps not superfluous to remind the student 
that, in the application of this Method, he should be 
peculiarly careful not to overlook any instance in which 
the given phenomenon is unaccompanied by the other 
circumstance. Such an instance should at once lead him 
to suspect that some third common circumstance, which 



128 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

may be the trae cause (or effect) of the given phenomenon, 
has escaped his attention, but it does not necessarily vitiate 
his conclusion. If the given phenomenon be the conse- 
quent, and this other circumstance the antecedent, such 
an instance may only point to some other and independent 
cause of the phenomenon in addition to the cause he sup- 
poses himself to have ascertained. If, on the other hand, 
the given phenomenon be the antecedent, and this other 
circumstance the consequent, such an instance may only 
point to a counteracting cause which, in this exceptional 
case, frustrates the supposed effect. The only condition 
essential to an application of the Method of Agreement is 
that the cases on which the inference is founded shall 
present only two circumstances in common. It is not 
necessary that these circumstances should invariably be 
found in conjunction, provided that in the cases where 
they are found in conjunction no other common cir- 
cumstance can be detected. We shall recur to this sub- 
ject below '. 

In the statement of the Canon, we have thought it 
desirable to introduce the expression * with more or less 
of probability/ in order to show that, under no circum- 
stances, does an inference drawn in accordance with the 
Method of Agreement attain to absolute and formal cer- 
tainty, though, as we have seen, it may attain to moral 
certainty. 

As familiar examples of the employment of the Method 
of Agreement, the following may be adduced : — 

' See pp. I35~I37- 



METHOD OF AGREEMENT. 1^9 

A particular kind of food, whatever else I may eat 
or drink, and however various my general state of health, 
the temperature of the air, the climate in which I am 
living, and my divers other surroundings, invariably makes 
me ill; I am justified in regarding it as the probable 
cause of my illness, and avoid it accordingly. This 
example furnishes a good illustration both of the diflSculties 
and of the possible cogency of the Method of Agreement 
What made me ill may have been some different viand 
on each of two, three, or four occasions, but it is very 
unlikely, if the number of occasions on which the in- 
ference is based be considerable, that it has been a dif- 
ferent viand on each of them. 

I find that a certain plant always grows luxuriantly 
on a particular kind of soil; if my experience of the 
places, where the soil is to be found, be sufiicientiy 
large, I am justified in concluding that the soil possesses 
certain chemical constituents which are peculiarly favour- 
able to the production of the plant. 

Trade is observed to be in a languishing condition 
wherever there exist certain restrictions, such as high 
duties, difficulties thrown in the way of landing or loco- 
motion, &c. ; if it could be ascertained that these countries 
agreed in no other respect which could influence the 
condition of trade, except in being subject to these 
restrictions, it might be inferred that the commercial 
depression was due to the restrictions as a cause. 

In all these cases, it will be seen that the great diffi- 
culty consists in ascertaining that the supposed cause is 

K 



130 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

the only drcomstance, or the only material drcnmstance, 
which, in addition to the phenomenon itself, the \'arious 
instances possess in conmion. 

We now append a few instances of a less familiar cha- 
racter : — 

The occurrence of Aurora Borealis has, under meteo- 
rological conditions of very different character, been in- 
variably found to be accompanied by considerable mag- 
netic disturbances. It is rightly inferred that there is 
some causal connection between magnetic disturbance 
and the occurrence of the Aurora Borealis. 

It has been obser\'ed uniformly, and under a \'ariety 
of circumstances, that, wherever an indiscriminate sys- 
tem of almsgiving has pre\*ailed, the population has, 
sooner or later, become indolent and pauperised. 
This may be noticed especially in the neighbourhood 
of large monasteries, in parishes where large sums of 
money are distributed in the shape of ' ddes,' in places 
which are the residence of rich and charitable but 
injudicious persons, and the like. The reason is not 
(Mfikult to discover. The unfortunate recipients of the 
charity are left without the ordinary motives to exertion, 
and consequendy, when the abnormal supply ceases, or 
becomes loo small for the wants of an increased popula- 
tion, being without self-reliance or any special skill, they 
have no resource but beggary. 

After a variety of experiments on substances of the 
most different kinds, and under the most different cir- 
cumstances, it has been found that, as a body passes 



METHOD OF AGREEMENT. I3I 

from one degree of temperature to another, it invariably 
undergoes a change of Volume, though that change may 
not always be in the same direction, it being, in the great 
majority of cases, in the direction of expansion, but, 
occasionally, in that of contraction. Hence it has been 
inferred that change of volume is an invariable effect 
of change of temperature. It has been supposed by 
some writers on physics that we may go further than 
this, and state that augmentation of temperature is invari- 
ably followed by augmentation of volume, and diminution 
of temperature by diminution of volume, the exceptions 
of water® as well as of bismuth and of the casting-metals 
generally (which suddenly expand at the moment of 
solidification) being explained as anomalies due to some 
interfering cause. We are, however, at present so little 
acquainted with the intimate constitution of bodies, that 
it might be rash to state the proposition in this form, 
and, stated as above, it is open to no exception*. 

^ Water follows the general rule, and continues to contract in bulk 
as its temperature is lowered, till it reaches about 39° Fahrenheit or 4° 
Centigrade, when it begins to expand and continues to do so till after its 
conversion into ice, so that a given weight of water at the temperature 
(say) of 37°, or when frozen, occupies more space than it occupied at 
(say) the temperature of 40°. This anomaly is somewhat boldly ex- 
plained by Mr. Grove as due to the setting in of the process of crystalli- 
zation, which he supposes to begin at 39°, and to interfere with the 
ordinary law of contraction and expansion. (See Grove's Correlation of 
Physical Forces, fifth ed. p. 58, &c.) 

^ I adduce this as an example of the Method of Agreement rather 
than of the Method of Concomitant Variations, because the argument, 
as here stated, rests rather upon the variation of circumstances and the 

K 2 



l^Z INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

The following example, which also illustrates the 
caution necessary to be observed in framing a general 
proposition, is extracted from Sir John Herschel's Dt's- 
course on the Study of Natural Philosophy '^^ : — 

* A great number of transparent substances, when exposed 
in a certain particular manner, to a beam of light which has 
been prepared by undergoing certain reflexions or refractions 
(and has thereby acquired peculiar properties, and is said 
to be "polarized**), exhibit very vivid and beautiful colours, 
disposed in streaks, bands, &c. of great regularity, which seem 
to arise within the substance, and which, from a certain 
regular succession observed in their appearance, are called 
"periodical colours." Among the substances which exhibit 
these periodical colours occur a great variety of transparent 
solids, but no fluids and no opaque solids. Here, then, there 

great diversity of bodies in which the law is found to hold good, than 
upon the relation between the various degrees of expansion or contrac- 
tion and the various degrees of temperature in the same body. Had 
the stress been laid upon the latter consideration, the argument would 
undoubtedly have been an instance of the Method of Concomitant 
Variations. 

It frequently happens, in fact, that two or more Methods are com- 
bined in the same proof. In the present instance, as will be seen below, 
the argument as applied to each particular kind of body (mercury, for 
instance) is an argument based on the Method of Concomitant Varia- 
tions ; but when we proceed to extend the experiment to other bodies, 
and then argue from the variety of the bodies examined that a body, in 
passing from one degree of temperature to another, invariably undergoes 
a change of volume, it appears to me that we are no longer employing 
the Method of Concomitant Variations but the Method of Agreement. 
It must be borne in mind that the object of our enquiry is not strictly 
the effects of heat (for the total effects of heat, inasmuch as we cannot 
wholly exhaust any body of its heat, must be unknown to us), but the 
effects of a change of temperature. ^^ § 90. 



METHOD OF AGREEMENT. 1 33 

seems to.be sufficient community of nature to enable us to 
use a general term, and to state the proposition as a law, 
viz. transparent solids exhibit periodical colours by exposure 
to polarized light. However, this, though true of many, does 
not apply to all transparent solids, and therefore we cannot 
state it as a general truth or law of nature in this form; 
although the reverse proposition, that all solids which exhibit 
such colours in such circumstances are transparent, would 
be correct and general. It becomes necessary, then, to make 
a list of those to which it does apply ; and thus a great 
number of substances of all kinds become grouped together, 
in a class linked by this common property. If we examine 
the individuals of this group, we find among them the utmost 
variety of colour, texture, weight, hardness, form, and com- 
position; so that, in these respects, we seem to have fallen 
upon an assemblage of contraries. But when we come to 
examine them closely in all their properties, we find they have 
all one point of agreement, in the property of double re- 
fraction, and therefore we may describe them all truly as 
doubly refracting substances. We may, therefore, state the fact 
in the form, " Doubly refracting substances exhibit periodical 
colours by exposure to polarized light;" and in this form 
it is found, on further examination, to be true, not only for 
those particular instances which we had in view when we 
first propounded it, but in all cases which have since occurred 
on further enquiry, without a single exception; so that the 
proposition is general, and entitled to be regarded as a law 
of nature.' 

The experiments by which Dr. Wells ^* established his 

" Dr. Wells* Memoir on Ae Theory of Dew^ which had become very 
scarce, was reprinted by Longmans and Co. in 1866. It is very brief, 
and well deserves to be carefully read by every student of scientific 
method. Sir John Herschel (Natural Philosophy, § 168) speaks of the 
speculation as * one of the most beautiful spedmen^* \w& casL cai2^\.^ \scisi^ 



134 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

Theory of Dew afford a remarkable example of the 
Method of Agreement. By employing various objects 
of different material under a variety of circumstances, 
he showed that, whatever the texture of the object, the 
state of the atmosphere, &c., it is an invariable condition 
of the deposition of dew that the object on which it is 
deposited shall be colder than the surrounding atmo- 
sphere, the greater coldness of the object being itself 
produced by the radiation of heat from its surface. This, 
to quote the words of Sir John Herschel, is the case not 
only with ' nocturnal dew,' but with ' the analogous phe- 
nomena ' of * the moisture which bedews a cold metal or 
stone when we breathe upon it ; that which appears on 
a glass of water fresh from the well in hot weather ; that 
which appears on the inside of windows when sudden 
rain or hail chills the external air ; that which runs down 
our walls when, after a long frost, a warm moist thaw 
comes on.' 

It is by the Method of Agreement that we discover the 
symptoms of a disease, the signs of a political revolution, 
national characteristics, the collocation of parts in an 
animal or vegetable organism, the order of superposition 
among geological strata, grammatical rules, and the like. 

The first division of Bacon's insianticB solttarice coin- 
cides with the cases contemplated in the Method of 
Agreement, as the second coincides with the cases con- 

*of inductive experimental enquiry lying within a moderate compass.* 
Mr. Mill also employs it as one of his Miscellaneous Examples in 
ch. ix. 



METHOD OF AGREEMENT. 1 35 

templated in the Method of Difference. The example of 
the first is so remarkable both in itself, and as an antici- 
pation of Newton's Speculations on Colour, that we may 
adduce it as an additional instance of the Method of 
Agreement : — 

'Exempli gratia: si fiat inquisitio de natura colon's, 
instanitcB solttartce sunt prismata, gemmae crystallinae, quae 
reddunt colores, non solum in se, sed exterius supra 
parietem. Item rores, &c. Istae enim nil habent com- 
mune cum coloribus fixis in floribus, gemmis coloratis, 
metallis, lignis, &c. praeter ipsum colorem. Unde facile 
colligitur, quod color nil aliud sit quam modificatio ima- 
ginis lucis immissae et receptae: in priore genere, per 
gradus diversos incidentiae ; in posteriore, per texturas et 
schematismos varios corporis. Istae autem tnstanttce sunt 
soh'tartcB quatenus ad similitudinem*^' 

In attempting to ascertain the cause of a given effect, 
a, it may happen that we find a particular antecedent, 
A, frequently, but not invariably, accompanying it. If, 
in those cases which present both a and A, no other 
common circumstance can be detected, we may infer 
that A is probably a cause of a. We say * a cause,' for 
the fact that a may be present without A is a proof that 
A is not the only cause. Our meaning will be plain from 
the following example : — 

We compare instances in which bodies are known to 
assume a crystalline structure, but which have no other 
point of agreement ; in the great majority of instances, 

" Novum Organum, Bk. II. aph. xxii. 



136 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

though not in all, we find that these bodies have assumed 
their crystalline structure during the process of solidifica- 
tion from a fluid state, either gaseous or liquid, and, 
so far as we can ascertain, these cases have no other 
circumstance in common. From this it may be reason- 
ably inferred that the passage from a fluid to a solid 
state is a cause, though not the only cause, of crystal- 
lization^'. 

Again, when A is frequently, though not invariably, 
followed by a, and there is, so far as we can ascertain, 
no other common antecedent, we are justified in sus- 
pecting that A is a cause of a, and that, in the cases 
where a does not occur, the operation of A is counteracted 
by some other cause. If, for example, a certain occupa- 
tion or mode of living is found to be usually, though not 
invariably, attended by a particular form of disease, we 
seem to be justified in regarding this occupation or 
mode of living as a cause of the disease, and in ex- 
plaining the few cases in which the disease does not 
occur as due to exceptional and counteracting circum- 
stances. 

Similarly, when a and b are found in frequent, though 

^ This example is adopted, with considerable modifications, from one 
which occurs in Mr. Mill's Logic^ Bk. III. ch viii. §1. I am indebted 
to Sir John Herschel for pointing cut to me that Mr. Mill's example 
(which I htd originally adopted as it stood) is too broadly stated. * The 
solidification of a substance from a liquid [it should be fluid] state' 
is not *an invariable,' but only an usual * antecedent of its crystallization.' 
The reader will find several exceptions noticed in Watts* Dictionary of 
Cbemistry, art. Crystallization. 



METHOD OF AGREEMENT. 1 37 

not invariable, conjunction", and, in the cases where they 
are found together, there occurs, so far as we can ascertain, 
no other common circumstance, we are justified in suspect- 
ing that there exists some causal connection between them. 
The student who is acquainted with the science of 
Medicine, will find a good illustration of the extreme 
diflficulty attending the application of the Method of 
Agreement, as well as of the Joint Method of Agreement 
and Difference (to be noticed presently), in the disputes 
which still occur as to the cause of the mental disease 
which is known as Atactic Aphasia, that is, the condition 
in which, with reference to certain sounds, the patient has 
lost the power of co-ordinating the muscles of speech. 
The French physiologist, M. Broca, laid down the posi- 

'^ The invariable conjunction of two phenomena, when the presence 
of the one implies the presence of the other, and the absence of the one 
the absence of the other, is a case falling under the Double Method of 
Agreement, to be explained presently; but those cases in which we 
simply know that a given phenomenon is invariably preceded or in- 
variably followed by another fall under the Method of Agreement just 
discussed. If a given phenomenon is, so far as we know, invariably 
preceded by another, this fact justifies us in suspecting (though it does 
not prove) that the antecedent is not only a cause, but the only cause, 
of the given phenomenon. Such a conclusion can only be proved (even 
approximately) by the Double Method of Agreement, to be explained 
presently. It is not, however, as already pointed out, in the invariableness 
of the antecedence, but in the fact that the instances examined present, so 
far as we can ascertain, only two phenomena in common, that the cogency 
of the Method of Agreement consists. But of this fact invariableness of 
antecedence (or of consequence) furnishes one of the strongest proofs, 
inasmuch as it implies a very wide variation of circumstances, and hence 
the stress laid upon it in some of the examples adduced above« 



138 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

tion that this disease is invariably due to a lesion of the 
third frontal convolution of the left hemisphere of the 
brain, the disease being invariably attended by the specific 
lesion, and the lesion never occurring without the disease. 
His followers maintain that the instances are decisive in 
favour of this theory, while the apparent exceptions admit 
of a satisfactory explanation ; his opponents, on the 
other hand, assert that there are well-established cases 
both of atactic aphasia without the specific lesion, and 
of the lesion without aphasia^**. 



METHOD OF DIFFERENCE. 
CANON. 

If an instance in which the phenomenon under investi- 
gation occurs^ and an instance in which it does not occur, 
have every circumstance in common save one, that one oc^ 
curring only in the former ; the circumstance in which 
alone the two instances differ, is the effect, or catise, or a 
necessary part of the cause, of the phenomenon. 

The circumstances a, b, c are found in conjunction 
with d, e, f, and the omission or disappearance of the cir- 

^* See a paper by Dr. William Ogle in the St. George* s Hospital Reports^ 
vol. ii. ; a Pamphlet by Dr. Frederic Bateman of Norwich, published by 
J. E. Adlard, Bartholomew Close, London, 1 868 ; Dr. Reynolds' System 
of Medicine, vol ii. pp. 442-444; and various reports of discussions 
published in the Lancet and other medical journals. I have to thank 
my friends, Professors Acland and Rolleston, for their kindness in sup- 
plying me with information on this interesting subject, and regret that 
my space prevents me from pursuing it at greater length. 



METHOD OF DIFFERENCE. I39 

cumstance a is found to be attended by the disappearance 
of the circumstance d. It is inferred that a and d are 
so connected that one is cause (or a necessary part of 
the cause) and the other effect. If, moreover, it can 
be ascertained that a is the antecedent and d the con- 
sequent, or that, though there are instances in which d 
occurs without a, there are no instances in which a occurs 
without d, we may proceed to infer (in the latter case, on 
the ground that a phenomenon may have more than one 
cause, but that a cause, unless counteracted by some other 
cause, must be attended by its effect) that a is the cause, 
and d the eflfect. Similarly, if the circumstances a, b, c 
are found in conjunction with d, e, f, and the introduction 
of the circumstance x into the former set of phenomena 
is found to be attended by the appearance of the cir- 
cumstance y in the latter set of phenomena (so that they 
may be represented respectively as a, b, c, x ; d, e, f, y), 
it may be inferred that x and y are related as cause 
and eflfect, or, if x be the antecedent and y the con- 
sequent, or the appearance of x be invariably attended 
by the appearance of y while the appearance of y is 
not invariably attended by the appearance of x, that x 
is the cause and y the eflfect. The reasons on which 
the Canon rests are obvious. All other circumstances 
remaining the same, if the introduction or omission of 
any circumstance be followed by a change in the remain- 
ing circumstances, that change must be due to such 
introduction or omission, as an eflfect to a cause; or, 
if two new circumstances enter simulta\ve.o\js»Vj ^ ^^rs&^<^xiX 



140 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

producing any other change in the phenomenon, these 
two circumstances (except on the improbable suppo- 
sition that they are two causes exactly counteracting each 
other) must be related as cause and eflfect, though we 
may be unable to say which of the two is cause and 
which eflfect. * The Method of Agreement/ says Mr. 
Mill, * stands on the ground that whatever can be eli- 
minated, is not connected with the phenomenon by any 
law. The Method of Diflference has for its foundation 
that whatever can not be eliminated, is connected with 
the phenomenon by a law/ In the Method of Diflfer- 
ence, the instances agree in everything, except in the 
possession of two circumstances which are present in 
the one instance and absent in the other. In the Method 
of Agreement, the various instances compared (for here 
we generally require more than two instances) agree in 
nothing, except in the possession of two circumstances 
which are common to all the instances. ,One Method 
is called the Method of Agreement, because we compare 
various instances to see in what they agree ; the other 
is called the Method of Diflference, because we compare 
an instance in which the phenomenon occurs with 
another in which it does not occur, in order to see in 
what they diflfer. 

Instances of the Method of Diflference are not far 
to seek. A piece of paper is thrown into a stove; we 
have no hesitation in regarding its apparent consumption 
as the eflfect of the heat of the fire, for we feel assured 
that the sudden increase of temperature is the only new 



METHOD OF DIFFERENCE. I41 

circumstance to which the piece of paper is exposed, and 
that, therefore, any change in the condition of the paper 
must be due to that cause. A bullet is fired from a gun; 
or a dose of prussic acid is administered, and an animal 
instantly falls down dead. There is no hesitation in 
ascribing the death to the gun-shot woimd or the dose 
of poison. Nor is this confidence the effect of any 
special experience, for, if it were the first time that we 
had seen a gun fired or a dose of poison administered, 
we should have no hesitation in ascribing the altered 
condition of the animal to this novel cause; we should 
know that there was only one new circumstance operating 
upon it, and, consequently, that any change in its con- 
dition must be due to that one circimistance. In all these 
instances, there is the introduction of a new antecedent, 
X, to which the new consequent, y, must be due. But, 
if the omission of one circumstance be attended by the 
omission of another, we may argue with equal confidence. 
I withdraw my hand from this book which is resting 
upon it, and the book instantly falls to the ground ; there 
is no hesitation in referring the altered position of the 
book to the withdrawal of my support A man is de- 
prived of food, and he dies ; we have no hesitation in 
ascribing the disappearance of the phenomenon we call 
life to the withdrawal of the means by which it is main- 
tained. In these instances, we have certain antecedents, 
followed by certain consequents, and, observing the simul- 
taneous or successive disappearance of A and a, we have 
no hesitation in connecting the two as cause and effect. 



14a INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

All crucial instances (instantiae" crucis, as they are 
called by Bacon) are applications of the Method of Dif- 
ference. A crucial instance is some observation or ex- 
periment which enables us at once to decide between two 
or more rival hj^otheses. It will be familiar to every one 
in the form of the chemical test, as where we apply an 
acid for the purpose of determining the character of 
a metal, or a metal for the purpose of detecting latent 
poison. According to the metaphor, there are two or 
more ways before us, and the observation or experiment 
acts as a ' guide-post ' (crux) in determining us which to 
take. The following beautiful example of a Crucial 
Instance is borrowed from Sir John Herschel ^'^, 

^^ * Inter praerogativas instantianim ponemus loco decimo quarto in- 
stantias crucis; translato vocabulo a crucibuSj qux, erectae in biviis, indicant 
et signant vianim separationes. Has etiam instarUias decisorias, et judi- 
dales, et in casibus nonnullis instantias oraculi, et mandati, appellare con- 
suevimus. Earum ratio talis est. Cum in inquisitione naturse alicujus, 
intellectus ponitur tanquam in aequilibrio, ut incertus sit, utri naturanim 
e duabus, vel quandoque pluribus, causa naturae inquisitae attribui aut 
assignari debeat, propter complurium naturanim concursum frequentem 
et ordinarium; instantice crucis ostendunt consortium unius ex naturis 
(quoad naturam inquisitam) fidum et indissolubile, alterius autem varium 
et separabile ; unde terminatur quaestio, et recipitur natura ilia prior pro 
causa, missa altera et repudiata. Itaque hujusmodi instantise sunt max- 
imae lucis, et quasi magnae auctoritatis ; ita ut curriculum interpretationis 
quandoque in illas desinat, et per illas perficiatur. Interdum autem 
instantice crucis illae occurrunt et inveniuntur inter jampridem notatas ; 
at ut plurimum novae sunt, et de industria atque ex composito quaesitae 
et applicatae, et diligentla sedula et acri tandem erutae.' — Novum Orga- 
num, Bk. II. aph. xxxvi. 

1^ Discourse on the Study of Natural Pbilosopby, > 218. 



METHOD OF DIFFERENCE. I43 

* A curious example is given by M. Fresnel, as decisive, 
in his mind, of the question between the two great opinions 
on the nature of light, which, since the time of Newton 
and Huyghens, have divided philosophers ; ' — that is be- 
tween what is called * the emission theory,' according to 
which light consists of actual particles emitted from lumi- 
nous bodies, and what is called * the undulatory theory,' 
according to which light consists in the vibrations of an 
elastic medium pervading all space. 

*When two very clean glasses are laid one on the other, 
if they be not perfectly flat, but one or both in an almost im- 
perceptible degree convex or prominent, beautiful and vivid 
colours will be seen between them ; and if these be viewed 
through a red glass, their appearance will be that of alternate 
dark and bright stripes. These stripes are formed betfween 
the two surfaces in apparent contact, as any one may satisfy 
himself by using, instead of a flat plate of glass for the upper 
one, a triangular-shaped piece, called a prism, like a three- 
cornered stick, and looking through the inclined side of it 
next the eye, by which arrangement the reflection of light 
from the upper surface is prevented from intermixing with 
that from the surfaces in contact. Now, the coloured stripes 
thus produced are explicable on both theories, and are ap- 
pealed to by both as strong confirmatory facts ; but there is 
a difference in one circumstance according as one or the other 
theory is employed to explain them. In the case of the 
Huyghenian doctrine, the intervals between the bright stripes 
ought to appear absolutely blacky in the other, half bright, 
when so viewed through a prism. This curious case of dif- 
ference was tried as soon as the opposing consequences of 
the two theories were noted by M. Fresnel, and the re- 
sult is stated by him to be decisive in favour of tj^a^ ^2c>si5sr^ 



144 INDUCTIVE METHODS, 

which makes light to consist in the vibrations of an elastic 
medium".' 

The following is an example of a similar kind. It had 
been determined, from theoretical considerations, that, on 
the assumption of the undulatory theory, the velocity of light 
must be less in the more highly refracting medium, while, 
according to the emission theory, it ought to be greater. 
When M. Foucault had invented his apparatus for deter- 
mining the velocity of light, it became possible to submit 
the question to direct experiment ; and it was established 
by M. Fizeau that the velocity of light is less in water (the 
more highly refracting medium) than in air, in the inverse 
proportion of the refractive indices. The result is, there- 
fore, decisive in favour of the undulatory, or at least, 
against the emission theory ^^ 

There is no science, perhaps, in which the Method 
of Difference is so extensively used as the science of 
Chemistry, and that because chemistry is emphatically a 
science of experiment. Almost any chemical experiment 
will serve as an instance of the Method of Difference. Mix, 
for example, chloride of mercury with iodide of potassium, 

^* Mr. Mill {Logic, Bk. III. ch. xiv. § 6) maintains that it does not 
follow from this experiment that * the phenomena of light are results of 
the laws of elastic fluids, but at most that they are governed by laws 
partially identical with these.* But though the experiment may not be 
decisive as in favour of the Undulatory Theory, it is undoubtedly de- 
cisive as against the Emission Theory. It may be necessary to add that 
the term * fluids* would now be repudiated by those who hold the 
Undulatory Theory. 

" See Lloyd's Wave Theory of Light, Art. 37 ; Ganot*s Physics, 
English translation, third edition, Art. 436. 



METHOD OF DIFFEREN'CE. I45 

and the result will be a colourless liquid at the top of 

the vessel with a brilliant red precipitate at the bottom. 

There can be no hesitation in ascribing this result to the 

mixture of the two liquids ; and two similar experiments 

will enable us to determine that the chlorine has been set 

free from the mercury and united with the potassium, 

which itself has been set free from the iodine with which 

it was previously imited, while the iodine has united with 

the mercury, the former producing chloride of potassium 

(dissolved in the colourless liquid), the latter iodide of 

mercury (the red precipitate). 

The science of Heat (or, as Dr. Whewell proposes to 

call it, Thermotics) also furnishes excellent examples of the 

Method of Difference. The following instances are adapted 

from Professor Tyndall's Ilea/ a Mode 0/ Motion^: — 

* Here is a brass tube, four inches long, and of three- 
quarters of an inch interior diameter. It is stopped at the 
bottom, and screwed on to a whirling table, by means of 
which the upright tube can be caused to rotate very rapidly. 
These two pieces of oak are united by a hinge, in which are 
two semicircular groves, intended to embrace the brass tube. 
Thus the pieces of wood form a kind of tongs, the gentle 
squeezing of which produces friction when the tube rotates. 
I partially fill the tube with cold water, stop it with a cork 
to prevent the splashing out of the liquid, and now put the 
machine in motion. As the action continues, the temperature 
of the water rises, and now the tube is too hot to be held in 
the fingers. Continuing the action a little longer, the cork 
is driven out with explosive violence, the steam which follows 
it producing by its precipitation a small cloud in the atmo- 
sphere.' 

» Third Edition, ch. i. |§ ii^-16. 

li 



146 INDUCTIVE METHODS, 

In this experiment it will be noticed that only one new 
antecedent is introduced, namely the motion of the ma- 
chine ; hence the increased temperature of the water and 
the various effects which follow upon it are due to the 
motion as a cause. The experiment, then, shows that 
heat is generated by the action of mechanical force. 

The converse of this proposition, namely that heat is 
consumed in mechanical work, or, as it is often stated, 
transmuted into mechanical energy, is proved by the two 
next experiments. 

*This strong vessel is filled at the present moment with 
compressed air. It has lain here for some hours, so that the 
temperature of the air within the vessel is now the same as 
that of the air of the room without it. At the present mo- 
ment this inner air is pressing against the sides of the vessel, 
and if this cock be opened a portion of the air will rush 
violently out. The word * rush,' however, but vaguely ex- 
presses the true state of things ; the air which issues is driven 
out by the air behind it ; this latter accomplishes the work of 
urging forward the stream of air. And what will be the con- 
dition of the working air during this process? It will be 
chilled. The air executes work, and the only agent it can 
call upon to perform the work is the heat to which the elastic 
force with which it presses against the sides of the vessel is 
entirely due. A portion of this heat will be consumed, and 
a lowering of temperature will be the consequence. Observe 
the experiment. I will turn the cock, and allow the current 
of air from the vessel to strike against the face of the pile '*^. 

^^ That is, the thermo-electric pile, a delicate instrument for indicating 
very small degrees of heat. It is by means of this instrument that it 
has recently been shown that we receive heat (though, of course, in in- 
finitesimal quantities) from the moon's rays. 



METHOD OF DIFFERENCE. 1 47 

The magnetic needle instantly responds ; its red end is driven 
towards me, thus declaring that the pile has been chilled by 
the current of air.* 

* Here moreover is a bottle of soda-water, slightly warmer 
than the pile, as you see by the deflection it produces. Cut 
the string which holds it, the cork is driven out by the elastic 
force of the carbonic acid gas ; the gas performs work, in so 
doing it consumes heat, and now the deflection produced by 
the bottle is that of cold.' 

The last experiment furnishes a good instance of the 
extreme simplicity of the examples by which scientific 
truths may often be illustrated. 

The uncertainty which, as we have seen, always at- 
taches to conclusions arrived at by the Method of Agree- 
ment renders it desirable that they should, wherever it is 
possible, be confirmed by an application of the Method 
of Difference. A beautiful instance of such a confirma- 
tion is adduced by Mr. Mill in the case of Crystallization. 
The Method of Agreement has already led us to the con- 
clusion that the solidification of a substance from a fluid 
state is a very frequent antecedent of its crystallization, 
and consequently, in all probability, one, at least, of its 
causes. But the Method of Difference completes the 
evidence, and enables us to state positively that it is 
a cause. 

* For in this case we are able, after detecting the antece- 
dent A, to produce it artificially, and by finding that a follows 
it, verify the result of our induction. The importance of 
thus reversing the proof was never more strikingly manifested 
than when, by keeping a phial of water ela.Ttg»^ 'wVCc^ ^^t^^^pos* 

L 2 



148 INDUCTIVE METHODS, 

particles undisturbed for years, a chemist (I believe Dr. Wol- 
laston) succeeded in obtaining crystals of quartz; and in 
the equally interesting experiment in which Sir James Hall 
produced artificial marble, by the cooling of its materials 
from fusion under immense pressure: two admirable ex- 
amples of the light which may be thrown upon the most 
secret processes of nature by well- contrived interrogation 
of her 22/ 

It will be noticed that the Method of Diflference is 
specially adapted to the discovery of the effects of given 
causes, whereas, where it is our object to discover the 
cause of a given effect, we are generally compelled to 
have recourse to the Method of Agreement. The Method 
of Agreement is, in fact, mainly a Method of Observation, 
whereas the Method of Difference is mainly a Method of 
Experiment. We may indeed arrange the conditions of 
an experiment so as to satisfy the requirements of the 
Method of Agreement, and Nature may (as in the familiar 
case of lightning) herself satisfy the requirements of the 
Method of Difference, but, as a rule, it will be found that 
arguments based on observations fall under the former, 
and arguments based on experiments under the latter 
Method. It is hardly necessary to add that, wherever we 
have our choice between the two methods, we should 
invariably select the Method of Difference. 

^ Mill's Logic y 6k. III. ch. viii. §1. I have been obliged, in accordance 
with what has been said on p. 136, to state, with considerable modifica- 
tions, the conclusion in this instance as arrived at by the Method of 
Agreement. The account of the application to it of the Method of 
Difference has been stated in Mr. Mill's own words. 



METHOD OF DIFFERENCE. 1 49 

In the employment of the Method of Difference, the 
greatest care should be taken to introduce only one new 
antecedent, or at least only one new antecedent which 
can influence the result. As the whole force of the 
argument based on this Method depends on the assump- 
tion that any change which takes place in the phenome- 
non is due to the antecedent then and there introduced, 
it is plain that we can place no reliance on our conclusion 
unless we feel perfectly assured that no other antecedent 
has intervened. If, for instance, it is our object to as- 
certain the heat of the atmosphere, we must take the 
greatest care that our thermometer is not affected by the 
heat radiated from or conducted by other bodies. The 
most curious examples of the disregard of this caution 
may be found in the History of Medicine. Something 
perfectiy inert has been administered to a patient in 
combination with some powerful drug, some important 
alterations in his diet, or some strict regime; then the 
effects of the drug, diet, or regime have been unwittingly 
ascribed to the inert substance. Had the ancients re- 
cognised that instead of one cause acting on falling 
bodies, as appeared to them to be the case, there were 
really two, the action of gravity tending downwards and 
the resistance of the atmosphere pressing upwards, they 
could never have fallen into the gross mistake of sup- 
posing that bodies fall in times inversely proportional to 
their weights. 



150 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 



DOUBLE METHOD OF AGREEMENT. 

CANON. 

If two or more instances in which the phenomenon occurs 
have only one other circumstance in common, while two or 
more instances from which the phenomenon is absent have 
nothing in common save the absence of that circumstance ; 
the circumstance in which alone the two sets of instances 
differ is the effect, or cause, or a necessary part of the cause, 
of the phenomenon. Moreover {supposing the requirements 
of the Method to he rigorously fulfilled), the circumstance 
proved by the Method to be the came is the only cause of 
the phenomenon. 

The uncertainty attaching to the Method of Agreement 
may, even where it is impossible to have recourse to the 
Method of Difference, be, to some extent, remedied by 
the employment of what is called by Mr. Mill the Joint 
Method of Agreement and Difference, or the Indirect 
Method of Diflference. This consists in a double employ- 
ment of the Method of Agreement and a comparison of 
the results thus obtained, the comparison assimilating it 
to the Method of Difference. We, first of all, compare 
cases in which the phenomenon occurs, and, so far as we 
can ascertain, find them to agree in the possession of 
only one other circumstance. But, though we may not 
be justified in regarding this inference as certain, we may 



DOUBLE METHOD OF AGREEMENT. 151 

increase our assurance by proceeding to compare cases 
in which the phenomenon does not occur. If these agree 
in nothing but the non-possession of the circumstance 
which the other cases agreed in possessing, we have a 
set of negative instances agreeing in nothing but the 
absence of the given phenomenon and the absence of 
the aforesaid circumstance. The set of negative instances 
may now be compared with the set of positive instances, 
and we may argue thus : The positive instances agree in 
nothing but the presence of the given phenomenon and 
this other circumstance, and the negative instances agree 
in nothing but the absence of the given phenomenon and 
this other circumstance. Hence we may regard it as a 
highly probable inference that they are connected together 
as cause and effect. We say * highly probable,' for, as we 
are not absolutely certain that the conditions of the Method 
of Agreement have been satisfied in the case of the posi- 
tive instances, so, from the extreme difficulty of proving a 
negative, we must be still less certain that they have been 
satisfied in the case of the negative instances. What (in 
addition to another advantage, to be noticed presently) is 
gained by the Method is a sort of double assurance, so far 
as the assurance goes, -^the one set of instances agreed 
in nothing but the presence of the two circumstances, 
and if the other set of instances agreed in nothing but 
the absence of the two circumstances, then we should 
be able to infer, by the Method of Difference, that the 
introduction of the given phenomenon (which we will 
suppose to be the consequent) is always v^^t^^'sjs&asj^:^ 



15a INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

by the introduction of the other circumstance (which 
we will suppose to be the antecedent), and, vice versd, 
that the removal of the given phenomenon is always 
necessitated by the removal of the other circumstance, 
or, in other words, that the given phenomenon is the 
effect and the other circumstance the cause. 

But this Method, supposing its conditions to be 
rigorously satisfied, possesses one advantage peculiar to 
itself. The Single Method of Agreement, as we have 
seen, is always theoretically open to the objection arising 
from Plurality of Causes, but this Method, if the set of 
negative instances be perfect, is not only free from that 
objection, but also sustains the conclusion that the in- 
ferred cause is the only cause of the phenomenon in 
question (or, in case we do not know which is ante- 
cedent and which is consequent, that a and b are 
so connected that one of them is the cause and the 
only cause of the other). * In the joint method,' says 
Mr. MilP^ *it is supposed not only that the instances 
in which a is agree only in containing A, but also 
that the instances in which a is not agree only in 
not containing A. Now, if this be so, A must be not 
only the cause of a, but the only possible cause : for 
if there were another, as for example B, then in the 
instances in which a is not, B must have been absent 
as well as A, and it would not be true that these instances 
agree only in not containing A.* It may be asked, then, 

23 Mill's Logic, Bk, III. ch. x. § a. 



DOUBLE METHOD OF AGREEMENT. 1 53 

if the negative branch of the argument be so forcible, 
why should we employ the positive branch? It is by 
means of the positive branch that we are, as it were, 
put on the track of the one other circumstance in which 
the instances presenting the given phenomenon agree, 
and by means of the negative branch that we prove the 
accuracy of our conclusion. ' It is generally,' continues 
Mr. Mill, * altogether impossible to work the Method of 
Agreement by negative instances without positive ones : 
it is so much more difficult to exhaust the field of ne- 
gation than that of affirmation.' 

It is plain that the conditions of the Joint Method can 
only be rigorously fulfilled where there is an invariable 
conjunction between two phenomena, so that the two are 
(unless counteracting circiunstances intervene) always 
present together and always absent together. For, if A 
be the only cause of a, the effect a cannot be present 
without the cause A, nor can the cause A be present 
without being attended by the effect a. Hence, invariable . 
conjunction may be regarded as a sign that the con- 
ditions of this Method are fulfilled, and it is from the 
observation of such an invariable conjunction that the 
argument frequentiy proceeds. In such cases, the niunber 
of instances, both positive and negative, which have been 
observed, is supposed to be so great and of such variety 
as to have excluded all other common circumstances 
except the presence or absence of the two phenomena 
in question. 

The Joint Method of Agreement axvd "DSSi^T^-w:.^ V^^^ 



154 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

the Indirect Method of Diflference, or, as I should prefer 
to call it, the Double Method of Agreement) is being 
continually employed by us in the ordinary affairs of life. 
If, when I take a particular kind of food, I find that 
I invariably suffer from some particular form of illness, 
whereas, when I leave it off, I cease to suffer, I entertain 
a double assurance that the food is the cause of my 
illness. I have observed that a certain plant is invariably 
plentiful on a particular soil ; if, with a wide experience, 
I fail to find it growing on any other soil, I feel con- 
firmed in my belief that there is in this particular soil 
some chemical constituent, or some peculiar combination 
of chemical constituents, which is highly favourable, if 
not essential, to the growth of the plant. 

Dr. Wells' Ussay on the Theory of Dew presents an 
'extremely instructive instance of the application of the 
Double Method of Agreement : — 

* It appears' (I am here quoting from Mr. Mill *) * that the 
instances in which much dew is deposited, which are very 
various, agree in this, and, so far as we are able to observe, 
in this only, that they either radiate heat rapidly or conduct 
it slowly : qualities between which there is no other circum- 
stance of agreement, than that by virtue of either, the body 
tends to lose heat from the surface more rapidly than it can 
be restored from within. The instances, on the contrary, 
in which no dew, or but a small quai^ity of it, is formed, and 
which are also extremely various, agree (as far as we can 
observe) in nothing except in not having this same property. 
We seem, therefore, to have detected the characteristic dif- 

2* MiU's Logic, Bk. III. ch. ix. § 3. 



DOUBLE METHOD OF AGREEMENT. 1 55 

ferenee between the substances on which dew is produced, 
and those on which it is not produced. And thus have been 
realized the requisitions of what we have termed the Indirect 
Method of Difference, or the Joint Method of Agreement 
and Difference.' 

Several beautiful illustrations of the Joint Method of 
Agreement and Difference may be found in the recent 
discoveries made by means of Spectrum Analysis. We 
shall select one which is peculiarly interesting on account 
of its employment in the attempt to determine the con- 
stitution of the Sim and some of the other heavenly 
bodies. 

A ray of light proceeding from incandescent hydrogen 
is passed through a prism, and it is invariably found that 
in the spectrum thus obtained there are two bright lines 
occupying precisely the same position. Moreover, rays 
of white Ught proceeding from various incandescent sub- 
stances are passed through incandescent hydrogen, and 
the emergent light is then broken up by a prism. In 
the spectra thus obtained it is foimd that there are 
invariably two dark (or, under certain circumstances, 
bright^) lines occupying exactly the same positions in 
the spectrum as the lines above mentioned. Hence it is 

^ The darkness of the lines is due to the property possessed by incan- 
descent media of absorbing rays of light of the same refrangibility as 
those emitted by them. When the absorption exerted upon the trans- 
mitted light is more than compensated by the luminosity of the hydro- 
gen light, these lines, instead of being dark, appear bright, as is also 
the case when the ray of light proceeds directly from incandescent 
hydrogen itself. 



156 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

inferred, by the Method of Agreement, that a ray of light, 
whether i proceed directly from incandescent hydrogen 
itself, or be transmitted through it from some other 
incandescent, substance, will invariably produce these two 
lines. But, if we try the same experiments with any 
other element than incandescent hydrogen, although we 
may obtain bright or dark lines, we never find these 
lines occupying the same positions in the . spectrum as 
the two lines in question. 

Here, then, we have the negative instances of the 
Double Method ; and it is inferred (subject, of course, to 
the assumption that our k owledge of the negative in- 
stances is sufficiently complete) that the presence in the 
spectrum of these two lines is invariably due either to a 
ray of light proceeding directly from incandescent hydro- 
gen, or to a ray transmitted through it from some other 
incandescent substance ; that is to say, that one or other 
of these is the cause, and the only cause of the presence 
in the spectrum of these two particular lines. When 
these lines are bright, it is doubtful whether the rays 
proceed directly from incandescent hydrogen or have 
been transmitted through it, but, when they are dark, 
the rays must have been transmitted. Wherever, there- 
fore, two dark lines occupying these positions occur in 
the spectrum we may infer (deductively) the passage 
of the ray of light through a medium composed wholly 
or partially of incandescent hydrogen. But we detect 
such lines in the spectrum of the sun and several of 
the stars, and hence (unless we suppose it possible or 



DOUBLE METHOD OF AGREEMENT, l^J 

not improbable that there is in the sun or other stars 
some element agreeing in this respect with hydrogen, 
but differing in others) we may conclude that the sun 
and these other stars are surrounded with an atmo- 
sphere of incandescent hydrogen^. 

The following examples are selected from a subject of 
a widely different character, the History of Language. 
M. Auguste Brachet, in his Historical Grammar of the 
French Tongue^, lays down that there are three sure tests 
by which we can discriminate between popular words 
derived from the Peasant Latin (lingua Latina rustica) 
by a regular process, and Latin words of learned origin 
imported into Modem French by scholars. These tests 
are (i) the continuance of the tonic accent; (2) the sup- 
pression of the short vowel ; (3) the loss of the middle 
or medial consonant. It will be seen that it is by the 
employment of the Double Method of Agreement that 
M. Brachet arrives at these conclusions. 

^ It must be understood that, in this example, I have not stated the 
historical steps by which the discovery was arrived at, but simply 
attempted to give a logical analysis of the arguments by which it would 
now be established. It may be added that the lines in question are 
known as C and F in the solar spectrum. It was the exact coincidence 
of the bright lines in the hydrogen spectrum with the dark lines C and 
F in the solar spectrum, which first led to the belief that hydrogen 
enters into the constitution of the solar atmosphere. It is now, how- 
ever, rendered possible, through an ingenious contrivance, to separate, as 
it were, the solar atmosphere from the glowing body within it, and thus 
to obtain these lines bright instead of dark. The student will find a brief 
account of these discoveries in Professor Stokes* Address to the British 
Association in 1869. ^ Mr. Kitchin's Ttwv,\V^\\o\v^^.'Xj'i« 



158 



INDUCTIVE METHODS. 



* Look at such words (i.e. words of popular origin) carefully, and you 
will see that the syllable accented in Latin continues to be so in French ; 
or, in other words, that the accent remains where it was in Latin. This 
continuance of the accent is a general and absolute law : all words be- 
longing to popular and real French respect the Latin accent : all such 
words as portique from pdrtious, or viatique from viaticum, which 
break this law, will be found to be of learned origin, introduced into the 
language at a later time by men who were ignorant of the laws which 
nature had imposed on the transformation from Latin to French. We 
may lay it down as an infallible law, that Tbe Latin accent continues in 
French in all words of popular origin ; all words which violate this law 
are of learned origin : thus — 



LATIN. 


POPULAR WORDS. 


LEARNED WORDS. 


Alt^mlne 


aliin 


alumine 


Angelus 


dnge 


angelus 


Bldsphemum 


blame 


blaspheme 


Cdnoer 


chancre 


cancir 


Odrnputimi 


cdmpte 


compUt 


D^bittun 


dette 


debit 


B^cima 
.... 


dime 

• • • • 


decime, &c. 

• • • 



* We have seen that the tonic accent is a sure touchstone by which to 
distinguish popular from learned words. There is another means, as 
certain, by which to recognise the age and origin of words — the loss of 
the short vowel. Every Latin word, as we have said, is made up of one 
accented vowel, and others not accented — one tonic and others atonic. 
The tonic always remains ; but of the atonies the short vowel^ which 
immediately precedes the tonic vowels always disappears in French: 
as in — 



Bon(i)tdtem 

San(i)t&teni 

Pos(i)ttira 

Clar(i)t&tem 

Sep(tl)in^uia 

Coin(i)t&tu8 

Pop(u)16tus 



bontd 

santd 

posture 

clart4 

semaine (O. Fr. sepmaine) 

comte 

peupld, &c. 



' Words such as circuler, ciroiil&re, which break this law and keep 



DOUBLE METHOD OF AGREEMENT. 



159 



the short vowel, are always of learned origin ; all words of popular origin 
lose it, as cereler. This will be seen from the following examples : — 



LATIN. POPXJLAR WORDS. LF.ARNED WORDS. 


Ang(a)latiui 


angU angule 


Bla8ph(S)mdTe 


blamer (0. Fr. blasmer) blaspbimer 


Oap(i)tae 


cbeptel capital 


Car(l)tdtem 


cberti cbarite 


Ciro(u)16re 

• • • 


cercler circtder, &c. 



* The third characteristic, serving to distinguish popular from learned 
words, is the loss of the medial consoi^nt, i.e. of the consonant which 
stands between two vowels, like the t in xnatiirus. We will at once 
give the law of this change : — All Frencb words wbicb drop tbe medial 
consonant are popular in origin^ wbile words of learned origin retain it. 
Thus the Latin vooalis becomes, in popular French, voyelle, in learned 
French vocale. There are innumerable examples of this : as — 



LATIN. 

Au(g)listii8 

Advo(c)&tii8 

Anti(p]i)6xLa 

Cre(d)6ntia 

Oomnium(o)&re 



POPULAR WORDS. 

aoUt 

avoui 

antienne 

creance 

communier 



LEARNED WORDS. 

auguste 

avocat 

antipbone 

credence 

communiquer, &c.' 



The requisitions of the Double Method of Agree- 
ment may be far from being rigorously fulfilled, and still 
two phenomena may be so frequently present together 
and so frequently absent together, that we may be justi- 
fied in suspecting some causal connection between them. 
Unless they were invariably absent together, as well as 
invariably present, and unless they were the only cir- 
cumstances which were invariably present and absent 
together, we should not be justified in regarding one as 
the cause, and the ortly cause, of the other ; but the mere 
detection of the fact that they are frequently ^!:^^^\5&. •iscA. 



l6o INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

absent together may justify us in believing that there 
is between them some causal connection. The precise 
character of this causal connection may hereafter be 
determined by one of the other inductive methods, or 
by bringing the case under a previous deduction. The 
following instances will serve as illustrations of what has 
been here said. 

Sir John Herschel conceives that he has detected a 
connection between a full moon and a calm night : * The 
only effect distinctly connected with its [the moon's] 
position with regard to the sun, which can be reckoned 
upon with any degree of certainty, is its tendency to clear 
the sky of cloud, and to produce not only a serene but a 
calm night, when so near the full as to appear round to 
the eye — a tendency of which we have assured ourselves 
by long-continued and registered observation.' The pre- 
cise nature of the causal connection can here be deter- 
mined: *The effect in question, so far as the clearance 
of the sky is concerned, is traceable to a distinct physical 
cause, the warmth radiated from its [the full moon's] 
highly -heated surface; though why the effect should 
not continue for several nights after the full, remains 
problematic*^.' 

In this example, there is not, of course, an invariable 
connection between the clear night and the full moon; 
for, in the determination of the weather, there are so 
many and so various causes at work that they must 
necessarily modify or counteract each other. The moon 

^* HerscheVs Familiar Lectures on Scientific Subjects, pp. 146, 147. 



DOUBLE METHOD OF AGREEMENT. l6l 

might exercise considerable influence, might, as Sir John 
Herschel says, have a tendency to produce a cahn night, 
and still be overpowered by other influences. It is suflS- 
cient, in order to lead us to suspect some causal connec- 
tion between the two phenomena, that we should find a 
calm night proportionably oftener, and oftener in a con- 
siderable proportion, when there is a full moon than 
when there is not Thus suppose that, after a long 
series of observations of nights when there is a full 
moon, we find the proportion of calm nights to nights 
which cannot be called calm to be 5 to 2 (we are, of 
course, taking an imaginary case), and the proportion 
on ordinary nights to be 3 to 2, there can be little doubt 
that the full moon is, in some way or other, connected 
with the larger proportion of calm nights. 

The employment of the Double Method of Agreement 
may lead to the detection of facts of causation in many 
instances of a similar kind. Thus, suppose that, in a 
particular part of the country, a particular wind is found 
to be proportionably oftener attended with rain than 
other winds, we begin to suspect that there is some 
causal connection between rain and this wind, so that, 
when the wind blows, we may expect rain, at least with 
more confidence than when other winds blow ; and, if the 
proportion in which rain accompanies this wind be much 
greater than that in which it accompanies other winds, 
our expectation is proportionably strengthened, and we 
have no hesitation in speaking of the quarter from which 
the wind blows as * the rainy quarter/ In this casfc^^^ 



1 62 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

cause is, of course, to be sought in the character of the 
tract over which the wind blows. Similarly, if, after 
sufficiently long observation, we find the death-rate in 
some particular place decidedly larger than in the sur- 
rounding neighbourhood, we have no hesitation in ascrib- 
ing the fact to some peculiarity either in the place or the 
population, and we at once begin to consider whether 
there is anything exceptional in the soil, the climate, the 
habits or occupations of the people, and the like, which, 
either alone or in conjunction with other circumstances, 
would account for the phenomenon. 

In all cases of this kind, we are, as it were, set on the 
track of a cause by discovering that some phenomenon is 
present in a proportionably greater number of instances 
when some other phenomenon is present than when it is 
absent. The cause itself may hereafter be detected either 
by one of the other inductive methods, or by bringing the 
case under a previous deduction. Thus, we know that 
the surface of that part of the moon which we call ' full ' 
is highly heated, and that it is the tendency of warmth 
radiated from a highly-heated surface to clear the atmo- 
sphere. Hence the series of observed phenomena is 
accounted for by being brought deductively under pre- 
vious inductions. 



METHOD OF RESIDUES. 1 63 



METHOD OF RESIDUES. 



CANON. 



Subtract from any phenomenon such pari as is known 
by previous inductions to be the effect of certain antecedents ^ 
and the residue of the phenomenon is the effect of the re- 
maining antecedents. 

If the antecedents are A, B, C, D, and the complex 
phenomenon can be resolved into the consequents a, jS, 
y, 5, €, of which y, 5, e are ascertained by previous 
inductions to be due to C, D, then the remaining 
consequents a, /3 must be referred to the remaining ante- 
cedents A, B. Given that the total result is due to a 
certain number of antecedents, and that part of the result 
is due to a portion of those antecedents; the residue 
of the result must necessarily be due to the remaining 
antecedents. This rule appears so obvious as to be 
hardly worth stating; it has, however, as will be seen 
from the examples given below, been mainly instrumental 
in leading to many of the most important discoveries of 
modern times. ' It is by this process, in fact,' says Sir 
John Herschel'^, 'that science, in its present advanced 
state, is chiefly promoted. Most of the phenomena which 
nature presents are very complicated ; and when the 
effects of all known causes are estimated with exactness, 
and subducted, the residual facts are constantly appearing 

^ Discourse on the Study of Natural Pbilo&o^Vj, H '^'^- 

ML 2 



164 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

in the form of phenomena altogether new, and leading 
to the most important conclusions/ 

There is one difficulty connected with this Method. 
Subtraction being a deductive process, why is the Method 
of Residues included among the inductive methods ? 
The Method, it must be confessed, is strictly deductive, 
but, as it is applied to the result of previous inductions 
and generally suggests subsequent inductions, it may 
vindicate its claim to discussion in this place. It is by 
induction that we ascertain that y, 5, € are due to C, D ; 
by the Method of Residues we determine that the re- 
maining consequents a, /S must be due to the remaining 
antecedents A, B ; we then generally proceed to decide 
by one of the other inductive methods which of the 
remaining consequents is due to which of the remaining 
antecedents. 

The following are instances of the employment of the 
Method of Residues, and it will be noticed that the 
science of astronomy is peculiarly rich in such ex- 
amples : — 

* The return of the comet predicted by Professor Encke, 
a great many times in succession, and the general good agree- 
ment of its calculated with its observed place during any one 
of its periods of visibility, would lead us to say that its gravi- 
tation towards the sun and planets is the sole and sufficient 
cause of all the phenomena of its orbitual motion ; but when 
the effect of this cause is strictly calculated and subducted 
from the observed motion, there is found to remain behind 
a residual phenomenon i which would never have been otherwise 
ascertained to exist, which is a small anticipation of the time 



METHOD OF RESIDUES. 165 

of its reappearances or a diminution of its periodic time, which 
cannot be accounted for by gravity, and whose cause is there- 
fore to be inquired into. Such an anticipation would be 
caused by the resistance of a medium disseminated through 
the celestial regions; and as there are other good reasons 
for believing this to be a vera causa, it has therefore been 
ascribed to such a resistance^*.* 

*The planet Jupiter is attended by four satellites which 
revolve round it in orbits very nearly circular, and whose 
dimensions, forms, and situations with respect to that of the 
planet itself are now perfectly well known. The periodical 
times of their respective revolutions are also ascertained with 
extreme precision, and all the particulars of their motions 
have been investigated with extraordinary care and persever- 
ance. The three interior of them are so near the planet, and 
the planes of their orbits so little inclined to that in which it 
revolves round the sun, that they pass through its shadow, 
and therefore undergo eclipse, at every revolution. These 
eclipses have been assiduously observed ever since the dis- 
covery of the satellites, and their times of occurrence regis- 
tered. As they afford a means of determining the longitudes 
of places, the prediction beforehand of the exact times of their 
occurrence becomes an object of great importance : and it is 
evident enough that, all the particulars of their motions being 
known (as well as of that of the planet itself, and therefore of 
the size and situation of its shadow), there would be no diffi- 
culty in making such prediction (starting from the time of 
some one observed eclipse of each as an epoch) ; provided always 
each eclipse were seen at the identical moment fwhen it actually 
happened. Moreover, on that supposition, the times recorded 
of all the subsequent eclipses ought to agree with the times so 

** Herschcrs Discourse on the Study of Natural Philosophy ^ § 159. 
It will be noticed that Sir J. Herschel uses the expression ' vera causa ' in 
the sense of * an actually existing fact.' 



l66 INDUCTIVE METHODS, 

predicted. This, however, proved not to be the case. The 
observed times were sometimes earlier, sometimes later than 
the predicted ; not, however, capriciously, but according to a 
regular law of increase and decrease in the amount of dis- 
cordance, the difference either way increasing to a maximum, 
— then diminishing, vanishing, and passing over to a maxi- 
mum the other way, and the total amount of fluctuation to 
and fro being about i6™ 27". Soon after this discrepancy 
between the predicted and observed times of eclipse was 
noticed, it was suggested that such a disagreement would 
necessarily arise if the transmission of light were not instan- 
taneous. This suggestion was converted into a certainty by 
Roemer, a Danish astronomer, who ascertained that they 
always happened earlier than their calculated time when the 
earth in the course of its annual revolution approached 
nearest to Jupiter, and later when receding farthest : so that 
in effect the extreme difference of the errors or total extent 
of fluctuation — the 16™ 27" in question — is no other than the 
time taken by light to travel over the diameter of the earth's 
orbit, that being the extreme diflference of the distances of 
the two planets at different points of their respective revolu- 
tions. At present, in our ahnanacs a due allowance of time 
for the transmission of light at this rate, assuming a uniform 
velocity, is made in the calculation of these eclipses ; and the 
discrepancy in question between the observed and predicted 
times has ceased to exist ^®.* 

The circumstances which led to the discovery of the 
planet Neptune furnish, perhaps, the most striking in- 
stance of the employment of the Method of Residues. 
From the year 1804 it had been noticed that the orbit 
of the planet Uranus was subject to an amount of per- 

^ HerscheVs Familiar Lectures on Scientific Subjects^ p. 226, &c. 



METHOD OF RESIDUES. 167 

turbation which could not be accounted for from the 
influence of the known planets. 

* Of the various hypotheses formed to account for it 
(the perturbation), during the progress of its development, 
none seemed to have any degree of rational probability but 
that of the existence of an exterior, and hitherto undiscovered, 
planet, disturbing, according to the received laws of planetary 
disturbance, the motion of Uranus by its attraction, or rather 
superposing its disturbance on those produced by Jupiter and 
Saturn, the only two of the old planets which exercise any 
sensible disturbing action on that planet. Accordingly, this 
was the explanation which naturally, and almost of necessity, 
suggested itself to those conversant with the planetary per- 
turbations who considered the subject with any degree of 
attention. The idea, however, of setting out from the ob- 
served anomalous deviations, and employing them as data 
to ascertain the distance and situation of the unknown body, 
or, in other words, to resolve the inverse problem of pertur- 
bations, ^^ given the disturbances to find the orbit ^ and place in 
that orbit of the disturbing planet^"* appears to have occurred 
only to two mathematicians, Mr. Adams in England and 
M. Leverrier in France, with suflScient distinctness and hope- 
fulness of success to induce them to attempt its solution. 
Both succeeded, and their solutions, arrived at with perfect 
independence, and by each in entire ignorance of the other's 
attempt, were found to agree in a surprising manner when 
the nature and difficulty of the problem is considered ; the 
calculations of M. Leverrier assigning for the heliocentric 
longitude of the disturbing planet for the 23rd Sept. 1846, 
326' o', and those of Mr. Adams (brought to the same date) 
329° 19', differing only 3° 19'; the plane of its orbit deviating 
very slightly, if at all, from that of the ecliptic. 

* On the day above mentioned — a day for ever memorable 
in the annals of astronomy — Dr. Galle, one of tha ^&\x^^\^\snk^ 



1 68 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

of the Royal Observatory at Berlin, received a letter from 
M. Leverrier, announcing to him the result he had arrived 
at, and requesting him to look for the disturbing planet in 
or near the place assigned by his calculation. He did so, and 
on that very night actually found it, A star of the eighth mag- 
nitude was seen by him and by M. Encke in a situation 
where no star was marked as existing in Dr. Bremiker's 
chart, then recently published by the Berlin Academy. The 
next night it was found to have moved from its place, and 
was therefore assuredly a planet. Subsequent observations 
and calculations have frilly demonstrated this planet, to which 
the name of Neptune has been assigned, to be really that 
body to whose disturbing attraction, according to the New- 
tonian law of gravity, the observed anomalies in the motion 
of Uranus were owing ^.' 

Besides furnishing an instance of the Method of Residues, 
the above example is also a happy illustration of the com- 
bination of deduction with observation which has been 
so eminently fertile in astronomical research. 

* Almost all the greatest discoveries in astronomy have re- 
sulted from the consideration of what we have elsewhere 
termed residual phenomena, of a quantitative or numerical 
kind, that is to say, of such portions of the numerical or 
quantitative results of observation as remain outstanding and 
unaccounted for after subducting and allowing for all that 
would result from the strict application of known principles'^. 

** Herschel's Outlines of Astronomy ^ Fourth Edition, §§ 767, 768. 

^^ A very striking example of the employment of the Method of 
Residues is to be found in the recent investigations by which Mr. 
Huggins has shown that the slight deviation of the lines C and F in 
the spectrum of Sirius is to be accounted for on the supposition that 
the soiar system and that star are mutually receding from each other 



METHOD OF RESIDUES. 1 69 

It was thus that the grand discovery of the precession of the 
equinoxes resulted as a residual phenomenon, fronfi the im- 
perfect explanation of the return of the seasons by the return 
of the sun to the same apparent place among the fixed stars. 
Thus, also, aberration and nutation resulted as residual phe- 
nomena from that portion of the changes of the apparent 
places of the fixed stars which was left unaccounted for by 
precession. And thus again the apparent proper motions of 
the stars are the observed residues of their apparent move- 
ments outstanding and unaccounted for by strict calculation 
of the effects of precession, nutation, and aberration. The 
nearest approach which human theories can make to per- 
fection is to diminish this residue, this caput mortuum of 
observation, as it may be considered, as much as practicable, 
and, if possible, to reduce it to nothing, either by showing 
that something has been neglected in our estimation of 
known causes, or by reasoning upon it as a new fact, and on 
the principle of the inductive philosophy ascending from the 
effect to its cause or causes ^^.' 

*Many of the new elements of chemistry have been de- 
tected in the investigation of residual phenomena. Thus, 
Arfwedson discovered lithia by perceiving an excess of ^weight 
in the sulphate produced from a small portion of what he 
considered as magnesia present in a mineral he had analysed. 
It is on this principle, too, that the small concentrated residues 
of great operations in the arts are almost sure to be the lurk- 
ing places of new chemical ingredients : witness iodine, brome, 
selenium, and the new metals accompanying platina in the 
experiments of Wollaston and Tennant. It was a happy 

at the rate of 29*4 miles a second. A brief account of this speculation 
may be found in Professor Stokes' Address before the British Association 
in 1869. 

^ Herschel's Outlines of Astronomy^ ^ B^6. 



ft 



170 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

thought of Glauber to examine what everybody else threw 
away^.' 

'The unforeseen effects of changes in legislation, or of 
improvements in the useful arts, may often be discerned by 
the Method of Residues. In comparing statistical accounts, 
for example, or other registers of facts, for a series of years, 
we perceive at a certain period an altered state of circum- 
stances, which is unexplained by the ordinary course of 
events, but which must have some cause. For this residuary 
phenomenon^ we seek an explanation until it is furnished by the 
incidental operation of some collateral cause. For example, 
on comparing the accounts of live cattle and sheep annually 
sold in Smithfield market for some years past, it appears that 
there is a large increase in cattle, while the sheep are nearly 
stationary. The consumption of meat in London may be 
presumed to have increased, at least in proportion to the 
increase of its population ; and there is no reason for sup- 
posing that the consumption of beef has increased faster than 
that of mutton. There is, therefore, a residuary pheno- 
menon — viz. the stationary numbers of the sheep sold in 
Smithfield — for which we have to find a cause. This cause is 
the increased transport of dead meat to the metropolis, owing 
to steam navigation and railways, and the greater convenience 
of sending mutton than beef in a slaughtered state. 

'Again : on comparing the consumption of wine with that of 
spirits and beer in England during the last sixty years *, we 
find that the former has remained stationary, while the latter 
has undergone a great increase. The general causes, such as 
increase of population and wealth, which have increased the 

^ Herschel's Discourse on the Study of Natural Philosophy ^ § i6l. 

'* This was written in 1852. Since that time, owing to the reduction 
of the duties, the greater familiarity of Englishmen with foreign countries 
and habits, and, perhaps, the taste for a more refined style of living, 
the consumption of wine has enormously increased. 



METHOD OF RESIDUES, 171 

consumption of spirits and beer, have not increased the con- 
sumption of wine. For this residuary phenomenon, a special 
cause must be sought ; and it may be found principally in the 
alteration of habits among the upper classes with respect to 
drinking ^,' 

We shall conclude our instances with what Sir John 
Herschel truly calls *a very elegant example,' the diflfer- 
ence between the observed and calculated velocities of 
sound. We quote from Professor TyndalFs Lectures on 
Sound : — 

* I now come to one of the most delicate points in the 
whole theory of sound. The velocity through air has been 
determined by direct experiment ; but knowing the elasticity 
and density of the air, it is possible without any experiment 
at all to calculate the velocity with which a sound-wave is 
transmitted through it. Sir Isaac Newton made this cal- 
culation, and found the velocity at the freezing temperature 
to be 916 feet a second. This is about one-sixth less than 
actual observation had proved the velocity to be, and the 
most curious suppositions were made to account for the dis- 
crepancy. Newton himself threw out the conjecture that it 
was only in passing from particle to particle of the air that 
sound required time for its transmission; that it moved in- 
stantaneously through the particles themsehfes. He then sup- 
posed the line along which sound passes to be occupied by 
air-particles for one-sixth of its extent, and thus he sought to 
make good the missing velocity. The very art and ingenuity 
of this assumption were sufficient to ensure its rejection ; 
other theories were therefore advanced, but the great French 
mathematician Laplace was the first to completely solve the 

^ Sir George Comewall Lewis on the Methods of Observation and 
Reasoning in Politics, vol. i. p. 356. 



172 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

enigma. I shall now endeavour to make you thoroughly 
acquainted with his solution. 

* I hold in my hand a strong cylinder of glass, accurately 
bored, and quite smooth within. Into this cylinder, which 
is closed at the bottom, fits this air-tight piston. By push- 
ing the piston down, I condense the air beneath it; and 
when I do so heat is developed. Attaching a scrap of 
amadou to the bottom of the piston, I can ignite it by the 
heat generated by compression. Dipping a bit of cotton 
wool into bisulphide of carbon, and attaching it to the piston, 
when the latter is forced down, a flash of light, due to the 
ignition of the bisulphide of carbon vapour, is observed within 
the tube. It is thus proved that when air is compressed, heat 
is generated. By another experiment, I can show you that 
when air is rarefied, cold is developed. This brass box con- 
tains a quantity of condensed air. I open the cock, and 
permit the air to discharge itself against a suitable thermo- 
meter ; the sinking of the instrument declares the chilling of 
the air. 

*A11 that you have heard regarding the transmission of a 
sonorous pulse through air, is, I trust, still fresh in your 
minds. As the pulse advances, it squeezes the particles of air 
together, and two results follow from this compression of the 
air. Firstly, its elasticity is augmented through the mere 
augmentation of its density. Secondly, its elasticity is aug- 
mented by the heat developed by compression. It was the 
change of elasticity which resulted from a change of density 
that Newton took into account, and he entirely overlooked 
the augmentation of elasticity due to the second cause above 
mentioned. Over and above, then, the elasticity involved in 
Newton's calculation, we have an additional elasticity due to 
changes of temperature produced by the sound itself. When 
both are taken into account, the calculated and the observed 
velocity agree perfectly '^.' 

^ Lectures on Sounds ch. i. 



METHOD OF CONCOMITANT VARIATIONS. 173 

It is not necessary, for our purposes, to pursue the 
quotation, but the student who wishes to see an example 
of the extreme delicacy and caution with which it is 
requisite to conduct physical researches, may with great 
advantage read the remainder of the chapter. 



METHOD OF CONCOMITANT VARIATIONS. 

CANON. 

Whatever phenomenon varies in any manner whenever 
another phenomenon varies in some particular manner, is 
either a cause or an effect of that phenomenon^ or is connected 
with it through some fact of causation: 



,37 



This Method is really a peculiar application, or series 
of applications, of the Method of Difference. It is em- 
ployed in those cases where a phenomenon cannot be 
made to disappear altogether, but where we have the 
power of augmenting or diminishing its quantity, or at least 
where Nature presents it in greater or smaller amounts. 
Thus, suppose we drop a quantity of quicksilver into a 
glass tube, we shall find that every sensible augmenta- 
tion of the temperature of the surrounding atmosphere 
is accompanied by a sensible augmentation of the volume 
of the quicksilver in the tube, and, vice versd, that every 
sensible diminution of the temperature is accompanied 

^ On p. 176 will be found a tvdai \a >&a%C.^v.wv, 



174 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

by a sensible diminution of the volume of the quicksilver. 
Now each particular experiment is an application of the 
Method of Difference, and, providing we have ascertained 
that the conditions of that Method have been rigorously 
satisfied, partakes of its cogency. That certain definite 
augmentations of temperature will increase the volume of 
quicksilver by, say, one-twentieth, one-thirtieth, or one- 
fiftieth part, is an absolutely certain inference, supposing 
due care to have been taken in the performance of the 
experiments, and is simply a result of the Method of 
DilBference. But, inasmuch as there are limits above and 
below which we cannot try the experiment, or inter- 
mediate points of temperature at which we do not find 
it convenient to do so, the question arises whether we 
are justified, in virtue of the experiments already tried, in 
asserting that the volume of the quicksilver will invariably 
expand or contract in proportion to the increasing 
or diminishing temperature of the surrounding media. 
We are justified in making such an assertion, and for 
this reason. The cause which occasions the quicksilver 
to expand or contract at two definite points must, if it 
continue to act, and if it be counteracted by no other 
cause, operate at all intermediate points ; and, similarly, 
the cause which occasions it to expand or contract up 
to a certain point must, on the same suppositions, go on 
producing a like effect. This is implied in the very 
notion of Causation. We arrive, then, at the conclusion 
that the volume of the quicksilver is invariably de- 
pendent on the temperature of the surrounding me- 



METHOD OF CONCOMITANT VARIATIONS. 1 75 

dhim ; in other words, that augmentation of temperature 
is the cause of its expansion^. 

It may be asked, Why not employ the Method of 
Difference once and for all ? Because, ex hypothesis the 
phenomenon is one which is only capable of augmenta- 
tion or diminution, and cannot be made to vanish. We 
may reduce to a minimum the resistance to motion, but 
we cannot remove the resistance altogether. We may 
more and more diminish the heat of a body, but we 
cannot wholly deprive the body of its heat. Hence we 
can apply the Method of Diflference to the several aug- 
mentations and diminutions of the phenomenon, but we 
cannot apply it to the phenomenon as a whole. 

In the example given above, we know that augmenta- 
tion of temperature and augmentation of volume are 
related as cause and effect, because, in the experiments, 
we can assure ourselves that they are the only two cir- 
cumstances which vary in common; if we were not 
certain of this fact, there might be some third circum- 
stance which was the cause of both. Moreover, we know 
that augmentation of temperature is the cause and aug- 
mentation of volume the effect, because, in this case, the 
former is the antecedent and the latter the consequent. 
There is another class of cases where, though we are not 
able to determine which of two circumstances is cause 

^^ The student acquainted with the phraseology of Mathematics will 
understand our meaning, when we say that the Method of Concomitant 
Variations is really an integration of a (supposed) infinite number of 
applications of the Method of Difference. 



176 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

and which is effect, we may regard the relation as being; 
one of cause and eflfect, inasmuch as we feel confident 
that there is present no third circumstance varying pro- 
portionately with the other two. But, if we cannot be 
confident even of this fact, the two circumstances may, 
for aught we know, both be effects of the same cause, 
as, for instance, the loudness of a clap of thunder varies 
with the intensity of a flash of lightning, though neither 
is the cause of the other, both alike being effects of the 
electrical condition of the atmosphere. Hence will be seen 
the importance of the concluding words of the Canon, * or is 
connected with it through some fact of causation.' The 
first and second cases differ from the third in this, that 
in both of them we suppose a rigorous fulfilment of the re- 
quisitions of the Method of Difference as applied to those 
individual observations or experiments on which the Method 
of Concomitant Variations is founded. In the last case, 
however, we suppose that there is some uncertainty as to 
whether the requisitions of the Method of Difference have 
been rigorously fulfilled or not. It will thus be seen that 
the statement of the Canon, as given above, is adapted 
to the weakest case. We may add to it the following 
rider : — 

I/we can assure ourselves that there is no third pheno- 
menon varying concurrently with these two, we may affirm 
that the one phenomenon is either a cause or an effect of 
the other. 

The Method of Concomitant Variations may be used 
for two purposes, either to establish a causal connection, 



METHOD OF CONCOMITANT tARlATIONS. JJJ 

or to detennine the law according to which two pheno- 
mena vary. Thus, it may either establish the fact that 
any increase of temperature causes quicksilver to expand, 
or it may determine the exact rate according to which 
this expansion takes place, a determination which is, in 
fact, eflfected by the ordinary thermometer. In the latter 
case, the application of the Method is not confined to 
those permanent natural agents, the influence of which 
we cannot altogether remove ; it may come in as supple- 
mentary to the Method of Difference. Thus it is by 
the Method of Difference that we discover that certain 
kinds of impurity in the atmosphere produce certain kinds 
of disease, but, if we could ascertain the relation subsisting 
between the amount of impurity in the atmosphere and 
the amount of disease, it would be by an application of 
the Method of Concomitant Variations. 

In the latter class of enquiries, the attempt to determine 
the nimierical relations according to wliich two pheno- 
mena vary, the utmost caution is required as soon as 
our inference outsteps the limits of our observations. In 
the first place, there is always the possibility of the in- 
tervention of some counteracting cause. In the case of 
water, we found that, at 39°, instead of continuing to 
contract as it becomes colder, it ceases at that point to 
do so, and thenceforward begins to expand. * No coun- 
teracting cause intervening' is, however, a qualification 
with which we must understand all our inductions, by 
whatever method they may have been arrived at. But 
there is an element of uncertainty which is peculiar to 

N 



178 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

the Method of Concomitant Variations as applied to 
determine the law or rate of variation between two 
phenomena, especially when the range of our obser- 
vations is confined within comparatively narrow limits. 
' Any one/ says Mr. Mill^, * who has the slightest acquaint- 
ance with mathematics, is aware that very different laws 
of variation may produce numerical results which differ 
but slightly from one another within narrow limits ; and 
it is often only when the absolute amounts of variation 
are considerable, that the difference between the results 
given by one law and by another becomes appreciable. 
When, therefore, such variations in the quantity of the 
antecedents as we have the means of observing are small 
in comparison with the total quantities, there is much 
danger lest we should mistake the numerical law, and 
be led to miscalculate the variations which would take 
place beyond the limits; a miscalculation which would 
vitiate any conclusion respecting the dependence of th^ 
effect upon the cause, that could be founded on those 
variations. Examples are not wanting of such mis- 
takes. " The formulae," says Sir John Herschel, " which 
have been empirically deduced for the elasticity of 
steam (till very recently), and those for the resistance 
of fluids, and other similar subjects," when relied on 
beyond the limits of the observations from which they 
were deduced, " have almost invariably failed to support 
the theoretical structures which have been erected on 

» MiU's Logic, Bk. III. ch. viii. § 7. 



METHOD OF CONCOMITANT VARIATIONS. 179 

them."' This, however, it must be noticed, is an un- 
certainty which does not vitiate the method, but simply 
renders necessary the exercise of the utmost caution in 
its application. 

Perhaps no simpler instance of the Method of Con- 
comitant Variations can be given than the experimental 
proof of the First Law of Motion, which Law may be 
stated thus : that all bodies in motion continue to move 
in a straight line with uniform velocity until acted upon 
by some new force. 

' This assertion,' I am quoting from Mr. Mill*^, * is in 
open opposition to first appearances; all terrestrial objects, 
when in motion, gradually abate their velocity and at last 
stop ; which accordingly the ancients, with their inductto per 
enumerationem simplicem, imagined to be the law. Every 
moving body, however, encounters various obstacles, as 
friction, the resistance of the atmosphere, &c., which we 
know by daily experience to be causes capable of destroying 
motion. It was suggested that the whole of the retardation 
might be owing to these causes. How was this enquired into ? 
If the obstacles could have been entirely removed, the case 
would have been amenable to the Method of Difference. 
They could not be removed, they could only be diminished, 
and the case, therefore, admitted only of the Method of 
Concomitant Variations. This accordingly being employed, 
it was found that every diminution of the obstacles diminished 
the retardation of the motion : and inasmuch as in this case 
(unlike the case of heat) the total quantities both of the 
antecedent and of the consequent were known ; it was prac- 
ticable to estimate, with an approach to accuracy, both the 
amount of the retardation and the amount of the retarding 

*• MiU's Logic, Bk. III. ch. viii. § 7, 
N 2 



l8o INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

causes or resistances, and to judge how near they both were 
to being exhausted ; and it appeared that the effect dwindled 
as rapidly [as the cause], and at each step was as far on the road 
towards annihilation as the cause was. The simple oscillation 
of a weight suspended from a fixed point, and moved a little 
out of the perpendicular, which in ordinary circumstances lasts 
but a few minutes, was prolonged in Borda's experiments to 
more than thirty hours, by diminishing as much as possible 
the friction at the point of suspension, and by making the 
body oscillate in a space exhausted as nearly as possible of 
its air. There could therefore be no hesitation in assigning 
the whole of the retardation of motion to the influence of the 
obstacles: and since, after subducting this retardation from 
the total phenomenon, the remainder was an uniform velocity, 
the result was the proposition known as the first law of 
motion.' 

We have already employed as an illustration the fact 
that a change in the temperature of a body is always 
accompanied by a change in its volume. The following 
extract places the same fact in a new light, and shows 
that the nature of substance (whether solid, fluid, or aeri- 
form) depends on, and, at considerable intervals, varies 
with, the temperature to which it is exposed. 

* The most striking and important of the effects of heat 
consist, however, in the liquefaction of solid substances, and 
the conversion of the liquids so produced into vapour. There 
is no solid substance known which, by a sufficiently intense 
heat, may not be melted, and finally dissipated in vapour ; 
and this analogy is so extensive and cogent, that we cannot 
but suppose that all those bodies which are liquid under 
ordinary circumstances, owe their liquidity to heat, and would 
freeze or become solid if their heat could be sufficiently 



METHOD OF CONCOMITANT VARIATIONS. l8l 

reduced. In many we see this to be the case in ordinary 
winters ; for some, severe frosts are requisite ; others freeze 
only with the most intense artificial colds; and some have 
hitherto resisted all our endeavours; yet the number of 
these last is few, and they will probably cease to be excep- 
tions as our means of producing cold become enlarged. 

*A similar analogy leads us to conclude that all aeriform 
fluids are merely liquids kept in the state of vapour by heat. 
Many of them have been actually condensed into the liquid 
state by cold accompanied with violent pressure ; and as our 
means of applying these causes of condensation have improved, 
more and more refractory ones have successively yielded. 
Hence we are fairly entitled to extend our conclusion to those 
which we have not yet been able to succeed with ; and thus 
we are led to regard it as a general fact, that the liquid and 
aeriform or vaporous states are entirely dependent on /beat ; 
that were it not for this cause, there would be nothing but 
solids in nature ; and that, on the other hand, nothing but a 
sufficient intensity of heat is requisite to destroy the cohesion 
of every substance, and reduce all bodies, first to liquids, and 
then into vapour".' 

An interesting application of the Method of Concomi- 
tant Variations is found in the arguments by which it is 
estabhshed that refrigeration at night (when the sun's rays 
are withdrawn) is, cceterts paribus, proportional to the 
dryness of the atmosphere. Thus, in the British Isles, 
where the atmosphere almost always contains a large 
amount of aqueous vapour, the, difference between the 
temperature at day and night is comparatively slight, 
whereas, in countries far inland, where the atmosphere is 

*^ Herschcl's Discourse on the Study of Natural Pbilosopby^ §§ 357, 
358. 



1 82 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

extremely dry, the variations of temperature are compara- 
tively large. This phenomenon is due to the fact that 
masses of aqueous vapour, though they intercept, also 
radiate heat. Hence, while during the day they protect 
us from the excessive heat of the sun, they intercept the 
heat which is radiated from the earth's surface during 
the night, and, at the same time, return to it some 
portion of the heat they have absorbed during the day. 

*A freedom of escape,* says Professor Tyndall*^, 'would 
occur at the earth's surface generally, were the aqueous 
vapour removed from the air above it, for the great body 
of the atmosphere is a practical vacuum, as regards the 
transmission of radiant heat. The withdrawal of the sun 
from any region over which the atmosphere is dry, must 
be followed by quick refrigeration. The moon would be 
rendered entirely uninhabitable by beings like ourselves 
through the operation of this single cause ; with a radiation, 
uninterrupted by aqueous vapour, the difference between her 
monthly maxima and minima must be enormous. The win- 
ters of Thibet are almost unendurable, from the same cause. 
Witness how the isothermal lines dip from the north into 
Asia, in winter, as a proof of the low temperature of this 
region. Humboldt has dwelt upon the "frigorific power" of 
the central portions of this continent, and controverted the 
idea that it was to be explained by reference to the elevation ; 
there being vast expanses of country, not much above the sea- 
level, with an exceedingly low temperature. But not 'knowing 
the influence which we are now studying, Humboldt, I ima- 
gine, omitted the most potent cause of the cold. The refri- 
geration at night is extreme when the air is dry. The removal, 
for a single summer night, of the aqueous vapour from the 

^ Tyndall's Heat a Mode of Motion^ § 492. 



METHOD OF CONCOMITANT VARIATIONS. 1 83 

atmosphere which covers England, would be attended by the 
destruction of every plant which a freezing temperature could 
kill. In Sahara, where " the soil is fire and the wind is flame," 
the cold at night is often painful to bear. Ice has been formed 
in this region at night. In Australia, also, the diurnal range 
of temperature is very great, amounting, commonly, to be- 
tween 40 and 50 degrees. In short, it may be safely predicted, 
that wherever the air is dry^ the daily thermometric range will 
be great. This, however, is quite different from saying that 
where the air is clear y the thermometric range will be great. 
Great clearness to light is perfectly compatible with great 
opacity to heat ; the atmosphere may be charged with aqueous 
vapour while a deep blue sky is overhead, and on such occa- 
sions the terrestrial radiation would, notwithstanding the 
" clearness," be intercepted.' 

The science of Geology abounds in instances of the 
employment of the Method of Concomitant Variations. 
In fact, as the agents with which it is concerned, land and 
water, subsidence and elevation, deposition and denuda- 
tion, are constantly present and acting on the earth's 
surface, and as it is impossible to cause the influence of any 
one of them to vanish altogether, the geologist is compelled 
in his explanations and arguments to avail himself mainly 
of this method. The following extract from Lyell's Prin- 
ciples of Geology furnishes a good illustration, and will be 
peculiarly interesting to any one who has visited the 
place. It is designed as an explanation of the alternate 
subsidence and elevation of the famous temple of Jupiter 
Serapis, at Pozzuoli, on the Bay of Naples. 

< We can scarcely avoid the conclusion, as Mr. Babbage has 
hinted, " that the action of heat is in some way or other the 



184 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

cause of the phenomena of the change of level of the temple. 
Its own hot spring, its immediate contiguity to the Solfatara, 
its nearness to the Monte Nuovo, the hot spring at the baths 
of Nero, on the opposite side of the Bay of Baiae ; the boiling 
springs and ancient volcanos of Ischia on one side and Vesu-^ 
vius on the other, are the most prominent of a multitude of 
facts which point to that conclusion." And when we reflect 
on the dates of the principal oscillations of level, and the 
volcanic history of the country before described, we seem to 
discover a connection between each era of upheaval and a 
local development of volcanic heat, and again between each 
era of depression and the local quiescence or dormant condi- 
tion of the subterranean igneous causes. Thus for example, 
before the Christian era, when so many vents were in frequent 
eruption in Ischia, and when Avemus and other points in the 
Phlegraean Fields were celebrated for their volcanic aspect 
and character, the ground on which the temple stood was 
several feet above water. Vesuvius was then regarded as a 
spent volcano ; but when, after the Christian era, the fires of 
that mountain were rekindled, scarcely a single outburst was 
ever witnessed in Ischia, or around the Bay of Baiae. Then 
the temple was sinking. Vesuvius, at a subsequent period, 
became nearly dormant for five centuries preceding the great 
outbreak of 163 1, and in that interval the Solfatara was in 
eruption a.d. 1198, Ischia in 1302, and Monte Nuovo was 
formed in 1538. Then the foundations on which the temple 
stood were rising again. Lastly, Vesuvius once more became 
a most active vent, and has been so ever since, and during the 
same lapse of time the area of the temple, so far as we know 
anything of its history, has been subsiding. 

* These phenomena would agree well with the hypothesis, 
that when the subterranean heat is on the increase, and when 
lava is forming without obtaining an easy vent, like that 
afforded by a great habitual chimney, such as Vesuvius, the 
incumbent surface is uplifted, but when the heated rocks 



METHOD OF CONCOMITANT VARIATIONS. 1 85 

below are cooling and contracting, and sheets of lava are 
slowly consolidating and diminishing in volume, then the in- 
cumbent land subsides*'.' 

Laplace's Nebular Hypothesis, that stellar systems, like 
our solar system, are formed from the gradual condensa- 
tion of different nebular masses, is supported by an appeal 
to this method. ' We see,' conceives Laplace, ' among these 
nebulae' (which are diffused along the Milky Way), ' in- 
stances of all degrees of condensation, from the most 
loosely diffused fluid, to that separation and solidification 
of parts by which suns and satellites and planets are 
formed ; and thus we have before us instances of systems 
in all their stages ; as in a forest we see trees in every 
period of growth**.' 

Physiology (so far as it is based on Anatomy, as dis- 
tinct from direct experiment), for like reasons with 
Geology, mainly employs the Method of Concomitant 
Variations. It is very seldom, in this science, that we 
obtain a phenomenon present in one set of instances and 
entirely absent in another; but we frequently find a 
phenomenon which, within certain limits, presents itself 
in the most variable quantities. If, then, we find another 

• 

phenomenon varying as it varies, we may argue with 

^ Lyell's Principlet of Geology, tenth edition, ch. xxx. 

^ Whewell's iNTovMm CrganumRenovatum, Bk. III. ch. viii. sect. 2. § 9. 
This example is adduced by Dr. Whewell as an instance of what he calls 
the Method of Gradation, which, however, must not be confounded with 
Mill's Method of Concomitant Variations. The example, so far as it 
can be relied on, serves equally well as an instance of either. 



1 86 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

tolerable confidence that they either stand to each other 
in the relation of cause and effect, or are, at least, com- 
mon effects of some unknown cause. Thus, it appears 
to be established that, not only in different species, but 
in different individuals of the same species, there is some 
relation between the manifestations of intelligence and the 
amount of cerebral development, understanding the latter 
expression to include not only bulk of brain but also 
complexity and depth of convolutions. 

'With some apparent exceptions,' says Dr. Carpenter **, 
a classical authority on most physiological questions, 'which 
there would probably be no great difficulty in explaining 
if we were in possession of all the requisite data, there is a 
very close correspondence between the relative development 
of the Cerebrum in the several tribes of Vertebrata and the 
degree of Intelligence they respectively possess — using the 
latter term as a comprehensive expression for that series of 
mental actions which consists in the intentional adaptation 
of means to ends, based on definite ideas as to the nature 
of both.* 

And again : — 

* As we ascend the Mammalian series, we find the Cerebrum 
becoming more and more elongated posteriorly by the de- 
velopment of the middle lobes, and the intercerebral con- 
missure becomes more complete ; but we must ascend as high 
as the Camivora, before we find the least vestige of the 
posterior lobes; and the rudiment which these possess is so 
rapidly enlarged in the Quadrumana, that in some of that 
group the posterior lobes are as fully developed in reference 
to the Cerebrum as a whole, and as completely cover in the 



i5 



Carpenter's Principles of Human Pbystology, sixth edition. 1864. 



METHOD OF CONCOMITANT VARIATIONS. 1 87 

Cerebellum, as in the human subject. The attention which 
has yet been given to this department of enquiry, has not 
hitherto done more than confirm the statement already made, 
with regard to the general correspondence between the de- 
velopment of the Cerebrum and the manifestations of Intelli- 
gence ; very decided evidence of which is furnished by the 
great enlargement of the Cerebrum, and the corresponding 
alteration in the form of the Cranium, which present them- 
selves in those races of Dogs most distinguished for their 
educability, when compared with those whose condition ap- 
proximates most closely to what was probably their original 
state of wildness. 

* This general inference drawn from Comparative Anatomy, 
is borne out by observation of the human species. When the 
Cerebrum is fully developed, it offers innumerable diversities 
of form and size among various individuals ; and there are 
as many diversities of character. It may be doubted if two 
individuals were ever exactly alike in this respect. That a 
Cerebrum which is greatly under the average size is incapable 
of performing its proper functions, and that the possessor 
of it must necessarily be more or less idiotic, there can be 
no reasonable doubt. On the other hand, that a large, well- 
developed Cerebrum is found to exist in persons who have 
.made themselves conspicuous in the world in virtue of their 
intellectual achievements, may be stated as a proposition of 
equal generality.' 

Dr. Thurnam*^, taking the brain-weights of ten dis- 
tinguished men, who died between the ages of fifty and 
seventy, calculates the average weight of their brains 
to have been 54*7 ounces. The average weight of the 
brains of ordinary men, dying between the same ages, 

*« On the Weight of the Brain^ by John Thuniam, M.D, l^^-s^&ss^x 
J. £. Adlard. 1866. 



1 88 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

is 47*1 ounces. This gives in favour of * cultivated and 
intellectual man' an excess of 7*6 ounces, or 15 per 
cent. Though, as a general rule, the connection between 
intellectual and cerebral development appears to be sub- 
stantiated, we must, however, be very cautious in draw- 
ing any inferences as to particular cases. Megalo- 
cephaly, or pathological enlargement of the brain, is a 
' recognised disease, and is frequently attended with idiotcy. 
In this class of cases, no doubt, if our means of investi- 
gation were adequate, we should discover some peculiarity 
either in the chemical composition or in the anatomical 
structure of the brain which would enable us to explain 
the exceptions in conformity with the rule. 

It is, perhaps, needless to add that we are not justified 
in drawing any further inference from these data, than 
that the brain is the organ of intelligence, and that there 
is some definite relation between the organ and its 
functions. 

Another interesting application of the Method of 
Concomitant Variations may be found in one of the 
arguments by which the distinction between Formed and 
Germinal Material is established. Any piece of glandular 
tissue, if examined under a microscope, will be found 
to consist of two parts, one of which will take a tint 
from carmine, the other not. The portion which takes 
the tint is called Germinal, the portion which will not 
take it is called Formed Material. The former is living 
matter, capable of growth and germination; the latter 
is dead matter, capable of no change but decay. Now, 



METHOD OF CONCOMITANT VARIATIONS. 1 89 

if this distinction between the two kinds of matter be 
well founded, we may reasonably expect to find the ger- 
minal matter developed in much larger proportions in the 
younger than in the older specimens of animals and 
plants, and in what may be called the more active than 
in what may be called the more passive parts of animal 
and vegetable organisms. And this is the case. In the 
pith of rush, elder, &c. we find that, in the spring, there 
are many portions of the cells which will take the carmine 
tint ; in summer, few ; in autumn, none. In the 
crystalline lens of the eyes of young animals the portions 
which will take it preponderate, becoming proportionately 
fewer as we examine the eyes of older specimens. In 
the grey matter of the brain we find many parts which 
will take the carmine tint, in the white matter but few. 
In a grain of wheat, when formed, there is, in the peri- 
sperm, no portion which will take it, in the white matter 
but a- small portion, while in the embryo it is often 
difl&cult to discover any part which does not take it. 
These instances might be multiplied to any extent*^. 

In physiological and medical researches, we must be 
peculiarly careful to bear in mind that, though two pheno- 
mena may vary proportionately, it by no means follows 
that one is cause and the other effect They may both 
be common effects of the same cause. Thus, though the 
prevalence of cholera is said to be constantly attended 

^ The student will find this subject fully treated in Dr. Lionel Beale's 
Lectures on the Simple Tissue of tbe Human Body, and in, other works 
of the same author. 



190 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

by the appearance of certain low forms of organic life, 
namely, fimgi or phytozoa, it by no means follows that 
these fungi or phytozoa are the cause of cholera. Both 
phenomena alike may be effects of certain conditions of 
the atmosphere. Nothing but a direct experiment could 
determine between these two theories. 

The Method of Concomitant Variations, or, as it is 
often called, when employed on subjects not strictly 
physical, the Method of Comparison, is that which is 
most frequently employed in the Science of Language. 
It is found, for instance, that between two dissimilar words 
employed at different epochs to express the same idea 
may be interpolated a number of intermediate forms 
employed at intermediate epochs, which make the transi- 
tion from the one word to the other gradual and natural. 
From this it is inferred that the word used at the later 
epoch is derived from that used at the earlier epoch, 
the lapse of time being regarded as the cause of the 
divergence. * Thus, at first sight,' says M. Brachet*^, 
'it is hard to see that dme is derived from anima; but 
history, our guiding-line, shows us that in the thirteenth 
century the word was written anniey in the eleventh aneme, 
in the tenth animey which leads us straight to the Latin 
anima* In this case there can be no doubt of the truth 
of the conclusion. 

Similarly, the loss of declension in the transition from 

** M, Brachet's Historical Grammar of the French Tongue, Mr. 
Kitchin's Translation, p. 42. 



METHOD OF CONCOMITANT VARIATIONS. 191 

the Latin language to the French is easily explained 
when we take into account the following considera- 
tions : — 

* The tendency to simplify and reduce the number of cases 
was early felt in the popular Latin : the cases expressed shades 
of thought too delicate and subtle for the coarse mind of the 
Barbarian. And so, being unable to handle the learned and 
complicated machinery of the Latin declensions, he constructed 
a system of his own, simplifying its springs, and reducing the 
number of the effects at the price of frequently reproducing 
the same form. Thus the Roman distinguished by means of 
case-terminations the place where one is, from the place to 
which one is going: "veniunt ad domum," "sunt in domo." 
But the Barbarian, unable to grasp these finer shades, saw no 
use in this distinction, and said, in either case alike, "sum 
in domum," " venio ad domum." 

'Thus, from the fifth centiuy downwards, long before 
the first written records of the French language, popular 
Latin reduced the number of cases to two: (i) the nominative 
to mark the subject ; and (2) that case which occurred most 
frequently in conversation, the accusative, to mark the object 
or relation. From that time onwards the Latin declension 
was reduced to this : — subject, muruj ; object, murum, 

* The French language is the product of the slow develop- 
ment of popular Latin; and French grammar, which was 
originally nothing but a continuation of the Latin grammar, 
inherited, and in fact possessed from its infancy, a completely 
regular declension : subject, murs, murus ; object, mur^ murum: 
and people said "ce murs est haut;" "j*ai construit un 



mur" 



* This declension in two cases forms the exact difference 
between ancient and modern French. It disappeared in the 
fourteenth century, not without leaving many traces in the 
language, which look like so many insoluble exceptions^ but 



1^2 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

find their explanation and historic justification in our know- 
ledge of the Old French declension *^* 

Here the conclusion is that French Grammar is derived 
from Latin Grammar, and that the lapse of time is the 
cause of the differences between them. 

Again, nothing at first sight would appear more im- 
probable than that the French word suz's and the Greek 
word cifu are derived from the same root. But, when 
we compare the Old French word sut\ the Latin sum, 
the Old Latin esunij and the Old Greek form eV/Lit, the 
connection of the two words and their ultimate derivation 
from a common root becomes a certainty. Here the 
divergence is accounted for not only by lapse of time, 
but by the various influences operating upon people (like 
the Latins and Greeks) occupying different tracts of 
country, exposed to different circumstances, having the 
organs of speech diflferentiy modified, and the like. 

Amongst the above examples it will be noticed that 
some have been included, the conclusions of which are 
by no means absolutely certain. In these cases, the 
deficiency of proof is due not to any formal inconclusive- 
ness in the Method of Concomitant Variations, or in that 
of Difference, on which it is based, but to the existence 
of a doubt as to whether the requirements of these 
methods have been stringently fulfilled. In any but the 
Experimental Sciences it is always extremely difl&cult to 

*• M. Brachet's Historical Grammar of the French Tongue, Mr. 
Kitchia's Translation, p. 88. 



METHOD OF CONCOMITANT VARIATIONS. 193 

assure ourselves that we are acquainted with all the cir- 
ciunstances which may influence, or may be influenced 
by, any given phenomenon. Moreover, as is the case, for 
instance, with regard to the concomitance between cere- 
bral development and the manifestation of intelligence, 
there may be many known points of difference between 
the observed cases besides those which are taken into ac- 
count, and the value of the conclusion will depend on the 
extent to which we have ascertained that these other points 
of difference are not pertinent, or not equally pertinent, 
with those which we have taken into account, to the cir- 
cumstance or circumstances which we are investigating. 

The application of the Method of Concomitant Varia- 
tions to determine the numerical relations subsisting 
between two phenomena may be illustrated from the ex- 
periments by which the measure of the accelerating force 
of gravity was established. The fact that the higher the 
point from which a body falls the greater is the velocity 
acquired is patent to observation, though, if we analyse 
the process by which we arrive at the conclusion, it 
is by the Method of Concomitant Variations. The rate 
of acceleration, however, is a very difl&cult and delicate 
problem to solve. By Attwood's machine (which it is 
unnecessary to describe here) it is shown (i) that gravity 
is an uniformly accelerating force, that is, that the incre- 
ments of velocity in equal times are equal ; (2) that the rate 
of increase varies slightly at different places on the earth's 
surface ; (3) that, in the latitude of Greenwich, in vacuo, 
and at high-water mark, the rate of acceleration for every 





194 . INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

second of time is 32*19 inches, the space traversed in the 
first second of time, if the body fall from rest, being half 
that quantity, so that the spaces traversed in successive 
units of time vary as the odd nimibers i, 3, 5 . . . . 
(2«— i). A slight degree of attention will show that 
it is by the Method of Concomitant Variations that all 
these conclusions are obtained ^. 

The conclusions based on statistics in moral and 
social enquiries are also instances of this application of 
the Method of Concomitant Variations. It is argued 
that, if the same causes continue to operate with like 
intensity and no new causes intervene, the numerical 
relations established between two classes of social pheno- 
mena, as, for instance, deficient education and crime, 
may be expected to remain constant. 

Briefly to review these Methods, it will be seen that 
we can only arrive at absolute certainty by means of 
one or other of the Methods of Difference, Residues, or 
Concomitant Variations, while the Method of Agreement 
and the Joint Method of Agreement and Difference give 
conclusions only of more or less probability, a probability, 
however, which sometimes amounts to moral certainty. 
The Joint Method of Agreement and Difference, or the 
Double Method of Agreement, possesses one advantage 
over all the other Methods, namely that, supposing it to 
have been satisfactorily ascertained by this Method that 

^ The student who wishes for more detailed information on this 
subject is referred to Professor Price's Infinitesimal Calculus^ vol. iii. 
chap, viii. sect. 3. 



INDUCTIVE METHODS. 1 95 

A is the cause of a, it will follow that it is the only 
cause. 

It should also be borne in mind that a wide distinction 
exists between those cases in which the induction indicates 
the precise character of the causal connection which 
subsists between two or more phenomena and those in 
which it simply points out that there exists a causal 
connection of some kind or other. In the latter case 
a new induction is required in order to show what the 
nature of the causal connection is. 

It may be noticed, finally, that the Inductive Methods 
are strictly reducible to two only, the Method of Agree- 
ment and the Method of Difference ; the Joint Method of 
Agreement and Difference being a double employment of 
the Method of Agreement, the Method of Concomitant 
Variations being a series of employments of the Method 
of Difference, and the Method of Residues being, strictly 
speaking, a deductive method employed in an inductive 
enquiry. 



Note I . — In the preceding chapter no allusion, or only 
a casual one, has been made to a circumstance which 
frequently occasions an insuperable difficulty in the appli- 
cation of the Inductive Methods, namely, the Intermixture 
of Effects. It has been supposed that the antecedents 
A, B, C, D, &c. are followed by the consequents a, j3, y, 8, €, 
&c,, the effects being regarded as heterogeneous and not 
homogeneous. But, suppose the effect o€ K.\.c>\ifc a^^"^\si 

o a 



196 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

be— ", of C to be y, of D to be ^, and of E to be — -, the 

total effect of A, B, C, D, E will be - + -^ . It is obvious 

how difl&cult it would be in this case to discover either 
the exact portion of the effect which is due to each cause 
or the several causes which operate to produce the total 
effect. We might have, in fact, as in mechanical action 
and reaction, A producing a and B producing — a, each 
cause thus neutralising the effect of the other, so that 
we might entertain no suspicion that the causes A and B 
were in operation at all. In these cases, our main re- 
source is Deduction combined with the Method of Re- 
sidues. Having ascertained separately by one or other 
of the various inductive methods, or from previous de- 
ductions, the effects, say of A, B, C, D, we calculate 
deductively their combined effect, and then, by subtracting 
the sum of the known causes from the total aggregate 
of causes and the known portion of the effect from the 
total effect, we simplify, if we do not solve, the problem. 
On the insufficiency, under ordinary circumstances, of the 
Inductive Methods, without the aid of Deduction, to 
grapple with cases of this kind, and on the nature of the 
assistance rendered by Deduction, the reader may con- 
sult Mr. Mill's Logic^ Bk. III. ch. x. § 4-8, and ch. xi. 

In cases of this kind, where the action of one cause 
is augmented, diminished, or wholly counteracted by that 
of another, it must not be supposed that any part of its 
appropriate effect has failed to be produced, even though 
it may have disappeared wholly or partially in the total 



INDUCTIVE METHODS. 1 97 

result. An object may remain at rest, . when subject 
to two equal forces acting in opposite directions, but 
we cannot say of either of these forces that it is in- 
operative : each, it is true, prevents any visible effect 
resulting from the other ; but then this is the very effect 
which it produces, and the correct mode of describing 
either of the opposing forces would be to say that 
it has a tendency to make the given object move with 
a certain velocity in a certain direction. The student 
cannot too constantly bear in mind that every cause has 
a tendency to produce its full effect, though other causes 
may prevent that effect from manifesting itself with all 
the intensity with which it would manifest itself, if it acted 
alone ; that there are, strictly speaking, no exceptions to 
laws of nature, though these laws, in their manifold action 
and reaction, may modify or even neutralise each other. 
The aphorism * Every rule has an exception,' is only true, 
even in Grammar, either because the rule is inexactly 
stated or because it conflicts with some other rule known 
or unknown. 

Note 2. — The Canons for the Inductive Methods were 
first stated by Mr. Mill, and the importance now attached 
to them in most analyses of inductive enquiries is mainly 
due to his influence. The methods are, however, as 
Mr. Mill himself states, ' distinctly recognised' in Sir John 
Herschel's Discourse on the Study of Natural Philosophy^ 
so often quoted in this work, 'though not so clearly 
characterised and defined, nor their correlation so fully 
shown, as has appeared to me desirabk.' Iw^^^^^^'^^ 



198 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

Book of Bacon's Novum Organum, we find some approxi- 
mations, very rough, it is true, to fonnal inductive me- 
thods. Tlie 'instantiae crucis' have akeady been adduced 
as examples of the Method of Difference, and the 'in- 
stantiae solitariae' as including examples of both the 
Method of Agreement and the Method of Difference ; 
but the part of the Novum Organum to which I am now 
alluding, and which is intended to be of more universal 
application than the ' instantiae crucis' and the 'instantia^ 
solitariae,' is contained in the early Aphorisms of the 
Second BooL Certain Tables of Instances are there 
given for the purpose of providing materials with which 
to conduct an investigation into what Bacon called the 
* Form,' corresponding pretty nearly to what we should 
call the 'Cause,' of Heat. The instances are very far 
from satisfying the conditions of Mr. Mill's Methods, but 
the principles on which they are arranged in Tables 
bear a close analogy to the principles on which the 
Canons are constructed. The best mode, perhaps, of 
enabling the student to perceive the extent of the resem- 
blance is to state the conditions with which the instances 
in Bacon's Tables would be required to conform, in 
order to satisfy the requirements of Mr. Mill's Methods. 

If the 'Instantiae convenientes in natura calidi'^^ were 
80 related to one another that, besides the given pheno- 
menon (heat), only one other circumstance were common 
to tbem all, that other circiunstance might be regarded, 



^ Nctmm Organum, Bk. II. Aph. zi. 




INDUCTIVE METHODS, 1 99 

with more or less probability, as the cause (or effect) of 
heat, or, at least, as connected with it through some fact 
of causation. Such instances would then come under the 
Method of Agreement. 

If one instance in the Table of Agreement (' Instantiae 
convenientes in natura calidi') were so related to one of the 
instances in the Table of Privation (' Instantiae in proximo, 
quae privantur natura calidi')^^ as to have every circum- 
stance in common with it, except that the former, besides 
presenting the phenomenon of heat which is supposed 
to be absent in the latter, also presented some other 
circumstance which was absent from the latter, this other 
circumstance would be the cause, or a necessary part of 
the cause (or effect), of heat. This would represent the 
Method of Difference. 

If, in the * Tabula graduum, sive comparativae in 
calido'^ we could discover some one phenomenon which 
increased or diminished proportionately with the increase 
or diminution of heat, that phenomenon would be the 
cause or the effect of heat, or, at least, connected with it 
through some fact of causation, and would answer to the 
Method of Concomitant Variations. If it could be shown 
that this phenomenon and heat were the only circum- 
stances which varied concurrently, then the phenomenon 
would be proved to be either the cause or the effect of 
heat, and would come under the rider to this last Method 
(p. 176). 

The * Exemplum exclusivae, sive rejectionis naturarum 

« Novum Organum, Bk. II. Aph, xiv. ^ \^. K^.tSv, 



aOO INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

a forma calidi'** bears some, though, it must be acknow- 
ledged, a very slight, resemblance to the Method of 
Residues. These *rejectiones' consist in excluding some 
possible explanation of the phenomenon, either because 
an instance, which does not present the phenomenon, 
does present the assigned cause, or because an in- 
stance, which does present the phenomenon, does not 
present the assigned cause*"*. As an instance of the 
former, we may take the following * rejectio' : * Per radios 
lunae (which were then supposed to be cold) et aliarum 
stellarum rejice lucem et lumen.' As instances of the 
latter, we may take the two following : * Per radios solis, 
rejice naturam elementarem (that is, * terrestrial nature,' 
which is composed of *the four elements'); Per ignem 
communem, et maxime per ignes subterraneos (qui re- 
motissimi sunt, et plurimum intercluduntur a radiis coeles- 
tibus) rejice naturam coelestem.' By a succession of these 
*rejectiones' we limit the number of possible explana- 
tions, amongst which we are to look for the true one. 
Bacon's * rejections,' however, lead to a purely negative 
result; they may save us from unnecessary trouble 
in seeking for a cause when it cannot be found, 
but they do not, like the Method of Residues, leave a 
definite number of antecedents which either constitute the 
cause, or amongst which we know that the cause is to 
be sought. 

** Novum OrganutUt Bk. II. Aph. xviii. 

** The latter, of course, is not a legitimate argument. The effect may 
be dne to seyera\ distinct causes, a fact which was not recognised by Bacon. 



INDUCTIVE METHODS. 201 

Note 3. — ^Dr. Whewell (in a pamphlet published in 
1849, which is now embodied in the Philosophy 0/ Dis- 
covery^ questions the utility of the Four Methods. 
* Upon these methods/ he says, * the obvious thing to 
remark is, that they take for granted the very thing which 
is most difficult to discover, the reduction of the pheno- 
mena to formulae such as are here presented to us/ He 
also objects that, as a matter of fact, no discoveries have 
ever been made by the employment of these methods. 
' Who will carry these formulae through the history of 
the sciences, as they have really grown up, and show us 
that these four methods have been operative in their for- 
mation ; or that any light is thrown upon the steps of 
their progress by reference to these formulae?' 

The first objection is, as Mr. Mill points out, of the 
same character with the objections raised by Locke and 
other writers of the eighteenth century against the Rules 
of Syllogistic Reasoning. The reply, in either case, is 
that Logic does not profess to supply arguments, but to 
test them. Men have certainly reasoned, and reasoned 
with the greatest force, without any conscious use of the 
rules of Logic. But it is the province of a system of 
Logic to analyse the arguments commonly, employed, to 
discriminate between those which are correct and those 
which are incorrect, and thus to enable men to detect, in 
the case of others, and to avoid, in their own case, 

^ See Pbilosopby of Discovery ^ ch. xxii. The criticism of Mr. Mill's 
Methods will be found in §§ 38-48. Mr. Mill replies in a note at the. 
end of 6k. III. ch. ix. 



202 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

erroneous methods of reasoning. To think of appro- 
priate arguments is undoubtedly more difficult than to 
test them ; but this does not obviate the necessity of sub- 
mitting them to a test. Nor is it a more real objection 
that men, who know nothing of the technical rules of 
Logic, often reason faultlessly themselves, and show re- 
markable acuteness in detecting inconclusive reasoning 
in the arguments of others. Many men speak grammati- 
cally without having learnt any system of grammar; in 
the same manner, many men reason logically without 
having leamt any system of Logic. But the great ma- 
jority of men, there can be little doubt, may derive 
assistance both from one and the other. Grammar 
fulfils its functions when it raises the student to the level 
of the most correct speakers ; similarly. Logic fulfils its 
functions when it raises the student to the level of the 
best reasoners. As applied to the syllogistic rules and 
formulae, this defence would now be generally admitted, 
but it holds equally good of the methods into which it 
may be shown that our inductive arguments may ulti- 
mately be analysed. * The business of Inductive Logic^' 
says Mr. Mill, * is to provide rules and models (such as 
the Syllogism and its rules are for ratiocination) to which 
if inductive arguments conform, those arguments are 
conclusive, and not otherwise. This is what the Four 
Methods profess to be, and what I believe they are 
universally considered to be by experimental philoso- 
phers, who had practised all of them long before any 
one sought to reduce the practice to theory/ 



INDUCTIVE METHODS. 203 

With regard to the second objection, that these me- 
thods have not been operative in the formation of the 
sciences, Dr. Whewell seems to ignore the distinction 
between the conscious and the unconscious employment 
of a method. It is undoubtedly true that in records of 
scientific investigations we seldom find the formal lan- 
guage in which the Inductive Canons are expressed. It 
seems to me equally true that in such records we inva- 
riably detect the employment of the Canons themselves. 
Discoveries are of two kinds : they are either entirely the 
result of patient research, or they are first suggested to 
the mind by some brilliant thought, and afterwards 
verified by rigorous proof. In the forrner case, the 
discoverer must have made sure of his ground as he 
proceeded, and, so far as his method was inductive, he 
could only do so by appealing, consciously or uncon- 
sciously, to one or more of the inductive methods ; if he 
acted otherwise, he arrived at a true result by mere 
accident. In discussing the latter case, we must repeat 
what has already been stated, that it is not the oflSce of 
Logic, either inductive or deductive, to suggest thoughts, 
but to analyse and to test them. Now, in the case we are 
supposing, the discovery really consists of two parts — 
the original conception and the subsequent process by 
which it is determined to be the true explanation of 
the phenomenon. However striking and appropriate 
the conception, we have no right to regard it as the 
true explanation of the phenomenon till it has been 
subjected to the most rigorous investl^tiQiT^.. 'Wsj&\!K5i^^- 



a04 INDUCTIVE METHODS. 

tigation must be either inductive or deductive, or both. 
But, so far as it is inductive, it must conform to the 
requirements of the Inductive Canons, or else it will not 
result in positive proof, or even approximate closely 
to it. As in the former case, imless the discoverer 
has, consciously or unconsciously, employed one or 
more of these Canons in the inductive part of his rea- 
soning, he has no right to feel any confidence in the 
result of his researches. 



-tr^QS^sy^'^^ 



CHAPTER IV. 
Of Imperfect Inductions. 

AN argument from the particular to the general, or 
from particulars to adjacent particulars, may fall short of 
absolute proof, or even of moral certainty, while it com- 
mends itself as possessing more or less of probability. 
Arguments of this character may be called Imperfect 
Inductions. Under this head fall imperfect applications 
of the experimental or inductive methods, the argument 
from analogy, and incomplete cases of Inductio per sim- 
plicem enumerationem. 

The Inductio per stmplicem enumerationem is, as al- 
ready noticed^, when complete, a deductive, and not an 
inductive, argument. When incomplete, it is an induc- 
tive argument, for it is an inference of the unknown 
from the known. This form of Induction possesses the 
force of demonstration only when, as in the case of the 
Laws of Universal Causation and of the Uniformity of 
Nature, it is grounded upon universal experience, and 

* Sec p. 117, note 2, and Deductive Logic, Part I I. chap. i. appended 
Note 2. 



2,o6 IMPERFECT INDUCTIONS. 

we feel assured that, if there had been at any time or 
were now in any place any instance to the contrary, it 
would not have escaped our notice. But, in ordinary 
cases, the incomplete Inductio per simplicem enumera- 
Honem affords only a presmnption, sometimes very slight, 
sometimes tolerably strong, in favour of the position 
which it is adduced to establish. I perceive, say in five, 
ten, or twenty cases, that the phenomenon a is attended 
by the phenomenon 3, and, knowing of no cases in 
which the one phenomenon is not attended by the 
other, I begin to suspect that a and h are connected 
together in the way of causation. Such a surmise may 
afterwards be proved by the aid of one or other of the 
five methods to be correct, and, in that case, it is taken 
out of the category of inductions per simplicem enumera- 
Honem J and becomes an instance of a scientific induction. 
But, if neither proved nor disproved, it still has a certain 
amount of probability in its favour, that amount depend- 
ing on the two following considerations: (i) the num- 
ber of positive instances which have occurred to us ; 
(2) the likelihood, if there be any negative instances, of 
our having met with them. The first of these considera- 
tions deserves little weight, unless supported by the other. 
A native of the North of Europe, some centuries ago, 
might, if the mere accumulation of positive instances were 
sufiicient, have taken it for a certain truth that all men 
had white complexions. His own personal observation, 
as well as the reports of travellers and the traditions of 
his race, would have furnished numberless instances in 



INDUCTIO PER SIMP. ENUM. 20J 

favour of the position. But, before drawing the inference, 
he ought to have reflected that he possessed information 
about a small portion only of the inhabitants of the 
earth's surface, that a difference of climate might produce 
a difference of complexion, and that there was no reason 
for supposing that the anatomical structure of man, or 
the various characteristics which we denominate human, 
are necessarily connected with a skin of one particular 
colour. But, on the other hand, we may affirm with 
tolerable certainty that all the varieties of beings pos- 
sessing the physical structure of man have the capacity of 
articulate speech ; for, if there were any races exhibiting 
the one set of phenomena without the other, there is 
every probability, with our present knowledge of the 
earth's surface, that we should be acquainted with their 
existence. In this instance the first consideration, which 
in itself would deserve little weight, is converted into a 
certainty almost absolute by the support which it derives 
from the second. 

It cannot be too strongly impressed on the mind of 
the student that a mere simplex enumeration that is, a mere 
assemblage of positive instances, unless we have reason to 
suppose that, were there any instances to the contrary, 
they would have become known to us, is simply worthless. 
' Inductio per simplicem enumerationem res puerilis est.' 
But if the simplex enumeratio be accompanied by a well- 
grounded conviction that there are no instances to the 
contrary, it may afford a very high degree of probability, 
and, if we can assure ourselves tiaaX ^^^x^ ^x^ \nk» '^sv- 



io8 IMPERFECT INDUCTIONS. 

Stances to the contrary, to us individually it will afford 
certainty. 

It might seem that an Inductio per Simplicem Enum- 
erationem is always an employment of the Method of 
Agreement. But there is this essential difference. The 
Inductio per Simplicem Enumerationem simply enume- 
rates instances without selection or precaution; whereas 
the whole force of the Method of Agreement consists in 
the choice and variety of the instances on which the in- 
ference is based. 

The term * Empirical Generalisation' or * Empirical 
Law' might be conveniently appropriated to express the 
result of an Inductio per Simplicem Enumerationem. 
Though these expressions are employed with great lati- 
tude, it is usually regarded as characteristic of an Em- 
pirical Law or Generalisation that it can only be received 
as true within the limits of the data from which it is 
derived, that at another time, at another place, or under 
different circumstances from those under which the 
observations were made, it might be found to break 
down^. It is true that, owing to the conflict of causes, 
this description applies to many of the conclusions arrived 
at by means of the Inductive Methods, but it is peculiarly 
applicable to the results of the Inductio per Simplicem 
Enumerationem, and it would be extremely convenient to 
possess an expression by which the results of this method 

^ See Herschel's Discourse on the Study of Natural Philosophy, § 187, 
and Miirs Logic, Bk. III. ch. xvi. § 4. 



ANALOGY. a09 

might be at once distinguished from those of scientific 
induction on the one hand, and those of analogy (to be 
discussed presendy) on the other. Instances of Empirical 
Laws in this restricted sense are such generalisations as that 
certain animals or flowers are of a certain colour, that 
certain tribes of men are less capable of civilisation than 
others, and, perhaps, that certain appearances of sky are 
indicative of certain changes ,of weather. There are, of 
course, some cases in which it is difficult to determine 
whether a given conclusion has been arrived at by the 
Inductio per Simplicem Enumerationem or by an imper- 
fect application of the Method of Agreement, that is to 
say, whether it is based on instances taken indifferently, 
or on selected instances ^ 

Another form of imperfect induction is the Argument 
from Analogy*. Here we do not argue from a niunber 

' I have ayoided any special discussion of what are called ' Empirical 
Laws/ both on account of the extremely indeterminate use of the ex- 
pression, and because such a discussion is calculated, in my opinion, 
needlessly to perplex the student by the complicated questions to which 
it leads. The advanced student can refer to Mr. Mill's Logic, Bk. III. 
ch. XV., and Bk. V. ch. v. § 4, but he will be introduced, I venture to 
think, to more difficulties than he will find solved. 

* It will be observed that the word 'Analogy* is here employed in the 
sense of ' resemblance.* In the stricter and more ancient meaning of the 
term, it signifies an equality of relations ({(T^n/t \6r^fw). See Aristotle's 
Ethics, Bk. V. 3. (8). The reader will find the two significations of the 
word 'Analogy* discriminated in the Elements of Deductive Logic, 
Part III. ch. i. note 2. 

Archbishop Whately defines Analogy as a Resemblance of Relations. 
This definition, if intended to represent the ancient sv^^&Ka^^ssa. ^sS. "^^ 

P 



a 10 IMPERTECT INDUCTIONS. 

of instances, as in the case of Inductio per Simplicem 
Enumerationem, but from a number of points of resem- 
blance. The argument is not, that because S, T, U, V, 
W, &c. exhibit the union of m with a, 3, r, we may 
therefore expect to find m in Z, or wherever else a, 
bf c may occur; but that, because X and Y (any two 
or more instances) agree in the possession of certain 
qualities a, 3, r, we may expect to find the quality m 
which is presented by X exhibited also in Y. The 
argument is based, not on the niimber of instances in 
which the two sets of qualities are found united, but on 
the number of qualities which are found to be common 
to two or more instances : the argument is not that 
I have so often observed a, 3, c in conjunction with m 
that I believe these qualities to be conjoined invariably, 
but that I know X and Y to resemble each other in so 

word, is incorrect. The Aristotelian Analogy is an equality^ not a 
resemblance of relations. The instance given in Etb. Nic. i. 6. (12) is 
that, in man, the reason {vovs) bears to the living principle (^wx^) the 
same relation that the faculty of vision {oipts) bears to the body {awpa) ; 
ofs ycLp kv aijiMTi &f/i9, iv ^vxj? ^ovs. The assertion, in this instance, it 
will be noticed, is that the relation to each other of the two former 
members of the analogy is, not similar to, but the same as, that of the 
two latter. The Aristotelian term avaXoylat in fact, exactly corresponds 
with the term Proportion as employed by mathematicians, and it was 
by the word Proportio, when not availing themselves of the Greek word 
Analogia itself, that the Romans expressed this form of argument. See 
Quinctilian, Inst. Or at. i. 6 : ' Analogic^ quam proxime ex Graeco trans- 
ferentes in Latinum proportionem vocaverunt, haec vis est : Ut id, quod 
dubium est, ad aliquid simile, de quo non quaeritur, referat ; ut incerta 
certis probet.' I am indebted for this quotation to Mr. Austin's Lectures 
on Jurisprudence t vol. iii. p. 255. 



ANALOGY. 2 1 I 

many points that I believe them to resemble each other 
in all. 

Thus, because the moon resembles the earth in being 
a large spheroid revolving round another body, as well 
as in various other particulars, it may be argued that 
it probably resembles the earth also in sustaining animal 
and vegetable life on its surface. But, if every ground 
of resemblance furnishes a probable reason for assigning 
to the one body any property known to belong to the 
other, it is evident that every ground of dissimilarity will 
also furnish a probable reason for denying of the first 
body any prpperty known to belong to the second. In 
estimating, therefore, the value of an analogical argument,, 
we must strike a balance between the known points of 
resemblance and the known -points of difference, and 
according as the one or the other preponderate, and in 
the proportion in which the one or the other prepon- 
derate, is the weight of the argument to be regarded 
as inclining. If, for instance, the phenomenon A is known 
to resemble the phenomenon B in four points, whereas 
the known points of difference between them are three, 
and it is discovered that some new property belongs to 
A but it is uncertain whether it also belongs to B, the 
value of the analogical argument that it does belong to 
B will be represented by 4 : 3. 

Before, however, we are justified in drawing this in- 
ference, it is necessary to observe certain cautions. 

In the first place, we must have no evidence that there 
is any causal connection between the ne^ ^\q^^\^?^ •xs:^ 

p 2 



212 IMPERFECT INDUCTIONS. 

any of the known points of resemblance or difference. 
If we have such evidence, the argument ceases to be 
analogical, and, if not a perfect induction, is an imper- 
fect induction of the kind to be described presently. 
We know, for instance, that animal and vegetable life on 
the surface of the earth could not exist without moisture ; 
but, so far as we are able to ascertain, there is no moisture 
on the surface of the moon. Hence we appear to be 
justified in concluding, not by analogy, but by the Method 
of Difference (assuming, of course, the accuracy of the 
observations), that animal and vegetable life, in the sense 
ordinarily attached to those terms, are not to be found on 
the moon's surface*. Again, we happen to know two men 
who bear a considerable resemblance to each other in 
character and opinions. One of these men acts in a par- 
ticular way, and we infer, analogically, that the other will 
act similarly. But, suppose we ascertain that the act of 
the former man was due to some particular characteristic, 
say avarice. The inference will now no longer depend 
on the ratio of the known points of resemblance to the 
known points of difference in the characters and opinions 
of the two men, that is, on analogy, but it will depend 
mainly on the presence or absence, the strength or weak- 
ness, of this particular characteristic in the second man, 

* See the Essay of the Plurality of Worlds (usually attributed to Dr- 
Whewell), ch. ix. sect. 7-9. The whole of this essay furnishes excellent 
examples of the employment of the Argument from Analogy, and also 
illustrates the extreme caution and delicacy which are requisite in esti- 
mating its value. 



ANALOGY. 213 

and, in a subsidiary degree, on the presence or absence, 
the strength or weakness, of corroborating or counter- 
vailing motives; that is, it will depend, not on analogy, 
but on other modes of induction. 

Secondly, though there must be no evidence to con- 
nect the property in question with any of the known 
points of resemblance or diflference, there must, on the 
other hand, be no evidence to disconnect it. If there 
be such evidence, the point of resemblance or diflference 
with which we know or believe it to be unconnected 
must, in estimating the value of the analogy, be left out 
of consideration. The reason is obvious. When we are 
enquiring whether this property is more likely to be 
connected with the known points of resemblance or the 
known points of diflference, it is plain that we must only 
take into account those points with which there is, at 
least, some chance of its being connected. 

Thirdly, we must have no reason to suspect that any 
of the known points of resemblance or diflference of 
which the argument takes account, are causally connected 
with each other. If the compared phenomena agree in 
the possession of the properties a, 3, c, </, e^ and of these 
properties b is an eflfect of (or causally connected with) 
a, and </ is an eflfect of (or causally connected with) r, 
the only properties which ought to be taken into account 
in estimating the value of the analogy are a, Cy e. The 
moon is supposed to diflfer from the earth in having 
no clouds and no water, but, as these two properties 
are mutually connected in the ^^^ ^ ^'»»&^ •m^^ 



214 IMPERFECT INDUCTIONS. 

effect, they can only be allowed to count as one 
item in instituting a comparison, for the purposes 
of analogy, between the known points of resemblance 
and the known points of difference in the two bodies. 
The enormous difference, on the other hand, between the 
maximum and minimum temperature of any place on the 
moon's surface, owing to the extreme length of the lunar 
days and nights, constitutes a distinct point of difference, 
and, as such, furnishes an additional argument against 
the habitation of the moon. When we ask to which 
side the argument from analogy inclines, we are asking 
whether it is more probable that the property in question 
(known to belong to the one phenomenon, but not 
tnown either to belong or not to belong to the other) is 
connected, by way of causation, with one of the known 
points of resemblance or with one of the known points of 
difference ; but, in calculating the probability, it is essen- 
tial that every point should, so far as we know, be in- 
dependent of every other ; for it is only in virtue of each 
being supposed to be an ultimate property or to point to 
an ultimate property that it has any claim to be taken 
into the account. Thus, if any two of the properties 
are found to be joint effects of the same cause or to 
stand to each other in the relation of cause and eflfect, 
they furnish only one argument instead of two. If we 
say of A that he is likely, under some particular con- 
juncture of circumstances, to act in the same manner as 
B, because they are both of them vain and selfish, we 
should not strengthen our argument by adding a number 



ANALOGY, 215 

of characteristics which are deducible from vanity and 
selfishness, or by adducing a number of individual acts 
in which these qualities have been exhibited. 

Fourthly, it is only when we have reason to suppose 
that we are acquainted with a considerable proportion of 
the properties of two objects, that the argument from 
analogy can have much weight. If we know only a few 
properties out of a large number, they may happen to be 
precisely those which are exceptional rather than repre- 
sentative, points of similarity where the objects themselves 
are mainly dissimilar, or points of dissimilarity where the 
objects are mainly similar. Thus, we know that in some 
respects the planet Mars closely resembles the earth, as, 
for instance, in having an atmosphere, a surface dis- 
tributed into land and water, and a temperature in which 
life similar to that on our own globe might exist ; 
but it would be very rask to conclude from these data 
that it also resembles the earth in sustaining animal and 
vegetable life on its surface ; for, though life, such as we 
understand it, does not appear to be impossible on the 
planet Mars as it is on many of the other celestial bodies, 
the number of properties with which we are acquainted is 
so small as compared with the number of properties with 
which we are unacquainted that there is little or nothing 
on which to ground a rational conclusion. On the other 
hand, the analogy by which Kepler boldly extended the 
three laws gained from the observation of the motion of 
Mars to the temaining planets was a perfectly sound one ; 
for the orbit of a planet, as compared with tke oftrwi^^^ 



2l6 IMPERFECT INDUCTIONS. 

of its surface, is a very simple phenomenon, and what was 
known of the orbits of the other planets made it appear 
more likely that they would correspond with the orbit 
of Mars than that they would differ from it. 

The value of the Argument from Analogy, then, we see, 
depends on the ratio of the ascertained points of resem- 
blance to (i) the ascertained points of difference, (2) the 
entire assemblage of the properties of the objects com- 
pared. If the ascertained resemblances are numerous, 
the ascertained differences, few, and we have reason to 
think that we are well acquainted with the objects com- . 
pared, the argument from analogy is very forcible. If, 
on the other hand, the ascertained resemblances only 
slightly exceed in number the ascertained differences, or 
if we have reason to suppose that there are numerous pro- 
perties in the compared objects with which we are un- 
acquainted, the value of the argfument from analogy may 
be very slight. It is commonly said that the value of an 
argiunent from analogy ranges from certainty to zero. 
If it reaches certainty, the argument becomes a com- 
plete induction; if it falls to zero, it ceases to be an 
argument at all ; if the probability is expressed by 
less than one-half, that is, if the number of ascertained 
resemblances be less than the number of ascertained 
differences, it is usual to say that analogy is against 
the possession by the one object of a quality known 
to belong to the other, or, in other words, in favour 
of their differing in the possession of this quality rather 
than agreeing in it. 



ANALOGY. 217 

* Besides the competition between analogy and diver- 
sity,' says Mr. Mill*, 'there may be a competition of 
conflicting analogies/ An object may be known to 
resemble one object in some particulars and another in 
others, and it may be a question with which of the two 
it ought to be classed, or which of the two it is likely to 
resemble in some unknown property. Thus, for some 
time it was a question whether a sponge was an animal 
or a vegetable substance ; and it is often by conflicting 
analogies that we attempt to determine to which of two 
or more masters a painting or a statue should be 
ascribed. 

The extreme caution which is requisite in employing 
the Argument from Analogy may be illustrated by the 
following scientific errors which have resulted from a 
hasty and inconsiderate employment of this mode of 
reasoning. 

Mr. Grove, in his Correlation of Physical Forces^ ^ while 
combating the once fashionable doctrine of electrical 
fluids, brings into juxta-position two very interesting 
instances of hasty analogies. 

* The progressive stages,' he says, * in the History of Phy- 
sical Philosophy will account in a great measure for the adop- 
tion by the early electricians of the theories of fluids. 

* The ancients, when they witnessed a natural phenomenon, 
removed from ordinary analogies, and unexplained by any 
mechanical action known to them, referred it to a soul, a 

• Mill's Logic, Bk. III. ch. xx. § 2. 
' Fifth edition, p. 135. 



2l8 IMPERFECT INDUCTIONS. 

spiritual or preternatural power : thus amber and the magnet 
were supposed by Thales to have a soul ; the functions of 
digestion, assimilation, &c., were supposed by Paracelsus to 
be effected by a spirit (the Archaeus). Air and gases were 
also at first deemed spiritual, but subsequently became in- 
vested with a more material character; and the word gas, 
from gehtf a ghost or spirit, affords us an instance of the 
gradual transmission of a spiritual into a physical conception. 

* The establishment by Torricelli of the ponderable cha- 
racter of air and gas, showed that substances which had been 
deemed spiritual and essentially different from ponderable 
matter were possessed of its attributes. A less superstitious 
mode of reasoning ensued, and now aeriform fluids were 
shewn to be analogous in many of their actions to liquids or 
known fluids. A belief in the existence of other fluids, differ- 
ing from air as this differed from water, grew up, and when a 
new phenomenon presented itself, recourse was had to a 
hypothetic fluid for explaining the phenomenon and connect- 
ing it with others ; the mind once possessed of the idea of a 
fluid, soon invested it with the necessary powers and pro- 
perties, and grafted upon it a luxuriant vegetation of ima- 
ginary offshoots.' 

Most of our readers will be aware of the difficulties 
experienced by the early geologists in accounting for 
the fact that the strata of our own and other northern 
countries often contain remains of animals and shells 
akin to those which are now to be found only in the 
torrid zone. This difficulty is easily explained by sup- 
posing a different distribution of land and water over the 
surface of the globe from that which at present exists. 
But we must pause before we admit the inference that, 
because these animals and shells are akm to those which 



ANALOGY. 219 

are now found only in warm climates, they must, there- 
fore, have subsisted in a similar temperature. 

*When reasoning on such phenomena,' says Sir Charles 
LyelP, * the reader must always bear in mind that the fossil 
individuals belonged to species of elephant, rhinoceros, hippo- 
potamus, bear, tiger, and hyaena, distinct from those which 
now dwell within or near the tropics. Dr. Fleming, in a 
discussion on this subject, has well remarked that a near 
resemblance in form and osteological structure is not always 
followed, in the existing creation, by a similarity of geo- 
graphical distribution; and we must therefore be on our 
guard against deciding too confidently, from mere analogy of 
anatomical structure, respecting the habits and physiological 
peculiarities of species now no more. " The zebra delights to 
roam over the tropical plains ; while the horse can maintain 
its existence throughout an Iceland winter. The buffalo, like 
the zebra, prefers a high temperature, and cannot thrive even 
where the common ox prospers. The musk ox, on the other 
hand, though nearly resembling the buffalo, prefers the stinted 
herbage of the arctic regions, and is able, by its periodical 
migrations, to outlive a northern winter. The jackal (Cams 
aureus) inhabits Africa, the warmer parts of Asia, and Greece ; 
while the isatis (Cams lagopus) resides in the arctic regions. 
The African hare and the polar hare have their geographical 
distribution expressed in their trivial names;" and different 
species of bears thrive in tropical, temperate, and arctic 
latitudes. 

* Recent investigations have placed beyond all doubt the 
important fact that a species of tiger, identical with that of 
Bengal, is common in the neighbourhood of Lake Aral, near 
Sussac, in the forty-fifth degree of north latitude ; and from 
time to time this animal is now seen in Siberia, in a latitude 

® Lyell's Principles of Geology, ch. vi. (ninth edition) ; cK« tl. (^vskc^x 
edition). 



220 IMPERFECT INDUCTIONS, 

as far north as the parallel of Berlin and Hamburgh. Hum- 
boldt remarks that the part of Southern Asia now inhabited 
by this Indian species of tiger is separated from the Himalaya 
by two great chains of mountains, each covered with perpetual 
snow, — the chain of Kuenlun, lat. 35° N., and that of Mouz- 
tagh, lat. 42°,— so that it is impossible that these animals 
should merely have made excursions from India, so as to 
have penetrated in summer to the forty-eighth and fifty-third 
degrees of nqrth latitude. They must remain all the winter 
north of the Mouztagh, or Celestial Mountains. The last 
tiger, killed in 1828, on the Lena, in lat. 5 2 J', was in a 
climate colder than that of Petersburg and Stockholm.' 

Neither in Analogy nor in Induction by Simple Enu- 
meration is there supposed to be any clue to a fact of 
Causation. When we begin to suspect that any one 
circumstance or set of circumstances is the cause or the 
effect of another, or connected with it in the way of 
causation, we ought at once to attempt to apply one or 
more of the Experimental Methods. If we can satisfy 
ourselves that their conditions, or those of any one of 
them, have been rigorously fulfilled, we have, of course, 
obtained a Valid Induction, giving us either absolute or 
moral certainty. But something considerably short of 
a rigorous fulfilment of these conditions may still lead 
to a conclusion, possessing more or less of probability. 
We may, for instance, to take the Method of Agreement, 
feel uncertain whether a and b (any two circumstances) are 
the only material circumstances which the cases we have 
examined exhibit in common; but still we may have 
examined so many, so various, and so well selected in- 



INCOMPLETE INDUCTIONS. 22t 

stances, that we may be justified in regarding it as highly 
probable that the two circumstances stand to each other 
in the relation of cause and effect, or are, at least, con- 
nected in the way of causation. Similarly, to take 
the Method of Difference, in the act of introducing 
a new antecedent, we may have unwittingly introduced 
some other new antecedent, or, in omitting an antecedent, 
we may have unwittingly introduced or omitted some 
other antecedent; but still we may have exercised such 
extreme caution as to justify us in feeling an assurance 
amounting almost, though not altogether, to certainty 
that the experiment has been rightly performed. The 
less our assurance of this fact, the slighter is the prob- 
ability of the conclusion. 

There remains one case, which is attended with some 
perplexity. It sometimes happens that, though we may be 
unable to establish a fact of causation between two par- 
ticular phenomena, we may be able to shew that some one 
phenomenon stands in a causal relation to some one or 
other of a definite number of other phenomena. Thus, 
supposing a vegetable to be transplanted to a distant 
part of the world, we may be able to assure ourselves, 
by excluding other causes of difference, that any new 
qualities which it may assume are due either to difference 
of climate, or to difference of soil, or to both these causes 
conjointly, though our knowledge may not enable us to 
assign amongst these alternatives the particular cause or 
combination of causes to which the effect \^ ^^. ^^-^ 



2M IMPERFECT INDUCTIONS. 

ought such an Inference to be classified as a perfect or 
an imperfect Induction? If we content ourselves with 
stating the alternatives, the inference should be regarded, 
so far as it goes, as a Perfect Induction ; for we do not 
state more than we conceive ourselves to be absolutely 
warranted in doing. But, if, on any grounds, we suppose 
one of these alternatives to be more probable than the 
others, and we state this as our conclusion, the inference 
is, of course, only a probable one, and should rank as 
an Imperfect Induction. 

The same remarks will apply to those cases in which 
there is any uncertainty as to the nature of the fact of 
causation. If the inference be, say, that the two pheno- 
mena either are one cause and the other eflfect, or stand 
to each other in the relation of cause and eflfect, though 
we may be unable to determine which of the two is 
cause and which is eflfect, or are joint eflfects of the 
same cause (adding any other alternatives which the par- 
ticular case may require), the inference is, so far as it 
goes, a Perfect Induction. But, if one or some only of 
these alternatives be selected, on any groimds short of 
absolute or moral certainty, to the exclusion of the 
others, the inference is only probable, and must be re- 
garded as merely an Imperfect Induction. 

Briefly to sum up the contents of this chapter. Imper- 
fect Inductions are the results either of an Inductio per 
Simplicem Enumerationem (to which we propose to ap- 
propriate the expression 'Empirical Generalisations'), or 



INCOMPLETE INDUCTIONS, 223 

of the Argument from Analogy (which we call Analogies), 
or of an imperfect fulfilment of one or other of the Induc- 
tive Methods (to which we might, perhaps, advantageously 
appropriate the expression 'Incomplete Inductions'). In 
the two former cases there is supposed to be no clue 
to a Fact of Causation, while in the last we conceive our- 
selves to be on the way towards establishing one. 



».«»«««««>• •**»»»»..,. 



CHAPTER V. 

On the relation of Induction to Dedtcction^ 

and on Verification. 

THE results of our inductions are summed up in 
general propositions, which are not unfrequently stated 
in the shape of mathematical formulae. These general 
propositions, the results of inductive reasoning, become, 
in turn, the data from which deductive reasoning pro- 
ceeds. Though the major premiss of any particular 
deductive argument may itself be the result of deduction, 
it will invariably be found, as pointed out long ago by 
Aristotle^, that the ultimate major premiss of a chain of 
deductive reasoning is a result of induction. There must 
be some limit to the generality of the propositions under 
which our deductive inferences can be subsumed, and, 
when we have reached this limit, the only evidence on 
which the ultimate major premiss can repose, if it depend 
on evidence at all, must be inductive. Thus, most of 
the deductions in the science of Astronomy, and many 

Ik tSjv Ka$6\ov. Eitrlv &pa dpxo^ k( &v 6 (rvWoyifffxds, S)v oit/e tan 
avXXoyi<rfJi6r (irayor^ &pa. — Eib. Nic, vi. 3 (3). Cf. Etb. Nic. vi. 6. 
8 (g) ; Metaphysics, i. I ; Posterior Analytics, ii. 19. 



RELATION OF INDUCTION TO DEDUCTION. 22^ 

of those in the science of Mechanics, depend ultimately 
on the Law of Universal Gravitation ; but this Law itself 
is the result of an induction based upon a variety of facts, 
including both the fall of bodies to the earth and the 
motion of the planets in their orbits. Again, a large 
number of geometrical deductions may be traced up to 
the ultimate major premiss : * Things that are equal to 
the same thing are equal to one another/ But this 
proposition, if not referred directly to induction, is 
classed under the head of intuitive conceptions, the most 
probable, though perhaps not the most commonly re- 
ceived, explanation of which is that which derives them 
from the accumulated experience of generations, trans- 
mitted hereditarily from father to son. 

A Deductive Inference combines the results of previous 
inductions or deductions, and evolves new propositions 
as the consequence, or, to put the matter in a slightly 
different point of view, as expressing the total result, 
of these combinations. We append a few easy examples 
of the manner in which the results of induction are em- 
ployed in a deductive argument. 

To begin with a very simple instance, but one which 
will serve as a good illustration of the stage at which 
our investigations cease to be inductive and become 
deductive; — suppose we have ascertained, by previous 
inductions, that A produces a, B produces b, C pro- 
duces — f, D produces |^, and E produces f, we know, 
by calculation, that is, by deductive reasoning, that the 
total effect of A, B, C, D, E is b -f ^. Iiv ^3ci^ ^•^^^ "^^ 



226 RELATION OF INDUCTION TO DEDUCTION, 

simple rules of Algebra, governing the addition and sub-^ 
traction of quantities, combined with the special data 
here furnished, are the premisses from which our de- 
ductive reasoning proceeds. 

The proposition proved in Euclid, Book i. Prop. 38, 
that * Triangles upon equal bases, and between the same 
parallels, are equal to one another,' is derived from, or 
is the total result of, the previous deductions (i) that 
* Parallelograms upon equal bases, and between the same 
parallels, are equal to one another,' (2) that * Triangles 
formed by the diagonal of a parallelogram are each of 
them equal to half the parallelogram' (i. 34), and (3) the 
previous induction that *the halves of equal things are 
equal.' 

What is called the Hydrostatic Paradox, namely, that 
a man standing on the upper of two boards, which 
form the ends of an air-tight leather bag, and blowing 
through a small tube opening into the space between the 
board, can easily raise his own weight, is a combination 
of two propositions, both gained from experience by 
means of induction, these propositions being (i) that 
fluids transmit pressure equally in all directions, (2) that 
the greater the pressure brought to bear on any surface 
from below, the greater the weight which it will sustain 
{otherwise expressed by the Mechanical Law that action 
and reaction are equal). 

To take another very simple instance of a similar kind. 
One of the earliest and easiest problems in the Science 
of Optics is the following : * A conical pencil of rays is 



AND VERIFICATION. 227 

incident upon a plane reflecting surface; to determine 
the form of the reflected pencil/ The solution, that the 
reflected pencil will be a cone having for its vertex a 
certain imaginary point, which can be geometrically deter- 
mined, on the other side of the surface, is derived from a 
combination of the experimental truth, gained by induc- 
tion, that ' the angle of reflexion is equal to the angle 
of incidence' with the geometrical propositions stated in 
Euclid i. 8 and i. 29. 

In the Science of Political Economy, Ricardo's Theory 
of Rent, namely that ' the rent of land represents the 
pecuniary value of the advantages which such land pos- 
sesses over the worst land in cultivation,' is an easy 
deduction from two principles which are supplied by 
every one's experience, namely, (i) that land varies in 
value, and (2) that there is some land either so bad or so 
disadvantageously situated as to be not worth the culti- 
vating^. 

Professor Cairnes' work on the Slave Power furnishes 
a remarkable example of the successful application of the 
deductive method to the determination of economical 
questions. The economical effects of slavery are thus 
traced. We learn from observation and induction that 
slave labour is subject to certahi characteristic defects: 
it is given reluctantly; it is unskilful; and, lastly, it is 
wanting in versatility. As a consequence of these cha- 
racteristics, it can only be employed with profit when 

' The student will find an easy exposition of this Theory in Fawcett's 
Manual of Political Economy ^ Bk. II. ch. iii. ad init. 



228 RELATION OF INDUCTION TO DEDUCTION, 

it is possible to organise it on a large scale. It re- 
quires constant supervision, and this for small numbers 
or for dispersed workmen would be too costly to be re- 
munerative. The slaves must, consequently, be worked in 
large gangs. Now there are only four products which 
repay this mode of cultivation, namely, cotton, sugar, 
tobacco, and rice. Hence a coimtry in which slave 
labour prevails is practically restricted to these four 
products, for it is another characteristic of slave labour, 
under its modern form, that free labour cannot exist 
side by side with it. But, besides restricting cultivation 
to these four products, some or all of which have a pe- 
culiar tendency to exhaust the soil, slave labour, from its 
want of versatility, imposes a still further restriction. 
* The difficulty of teaching the slave anything is so great 
— the result of the compulsory ignorance in which he is 
kept, combined with want of intelligent interest in his 
work — that the only chance of rendering his labour 
profitable is, when he has once learned a lesson, to keep 
him to that lesson for life. Accordingly where agricul- 
tural operations are carried on by slaves, the business of 
each gang is always restricted to the raising of a single 
product. Whatever crop be best suited to the character 
of the soil and the nature of slave industry, whether 
cotton, tobacco, sugar, or rice, that crop is cultivated, 
and that crop only. Rotation of crops is thus precluded 
by the conditions of the case. The soil is tasked again 
and again to peld the same product, and the inevitable 
result follows. After a short series of years its fertility 



AND VERIFICATION. 22,() 

is completely exhausted, the planter abandons the ground 
which he has rendered worthless, and passes on to seek 
in new soils for that fertility under which alone the 
agencies at his disposal can be profitably employed.' 
Thus, from the characteristics of slave labour may be 
deduced the economical effects of exhaustion of the soil 
on which it prevails, and the consequent necessity of 
constantly seeking to extend the area of cultivation. 
From the peculiar character of the crops which can 
alone be successfully raised by slave labour may be ex- 
plained the former prevalence of slavery in the Southern, 
and its absence in the Northern, States of the American 
Union ; and from the necessity of constantly seeking 
fertile virgin soil for the employment of slave labour may 
be explained the former policy of the Southern States, 
which was invariably endeavouring to bring newly consti- 
tuted States under the dominion of slave institutions^ 

These examples of the combination of inductive with 
deductive reasoning might be multiplied to any extent. 
Mechanics, Astronomy, and the Mathematico-physical 
sciences generally, furnish, perhaps, the most striking 
instances of them. The great importance of deduction 
as an instrument for the ascertainment of physical truths 
could hardly be illustrated more appropriately than by the 
following cases adduced by Sir John Herschel* : — 

^ See Professor Cairnes on the Slave Power, ch. ii. His arguments are 
stated in a condensed form in Fawcett's Manual of Political Economy, 
Bk. II. ch. xi. 

* Discourse on tbe Study of Natural PbUosopby, § 399. 



230 RELATION OF INDUCTION TO DEDUCTION, 

' It had been objected to the doctrine of Copernicus, that, 
were it true, Venus [and, it might have been added. Mercury, 
as the other inferior planet] should appear sometimes homed 
like the moon. To this he answered by admitting the con- 
clusion, and averring that, should we ever be able to see its 
actual shape, it would appear so. It is easy to imagine -with 
what force the application would strike every mind when the 
telescope confirmed this prediction, and showed the planet just 
as both the philosopher and his objectors had agreed it ought 
to appear. The history of science affords perhaps only one 
instance analogous to this. When Dr. Hutton expounded his 
theory of the consolidation of rocks by the application of heat, 
at a great depth below the bed of the ocean, and especially 
of that of marble by actual fusion ; it was objected that, 
whatever might be the case with others, with calcareous or 
marble rocks, at least, it was impossible to grant such a cause 
of consolidation, since heat decomposes their substance and 
converts it into quicklime, by driving off the carbonic acid, 
and leaving a substance perfectly infusible, and incapable even 
of agglutination by heat. To this he replied, that the pressure 
under which the heat was applied would prevent the escape 
of the carbonic acid; and that being retained, it might be 
expected to give that fusibility to the compound which the 
simple quicklime wanted. The next generation saw this an- 
ticipation converted into an observed fact, and verified by the 
direct experiments of Sir James Hall, who actually succeeded 
in melting marble, by retaining its carbonic acid under violent 
pressure.' 



The instances just adduced naturally lead to a discus- 
sion of the place to be assigned in scientific enquiry to 
the process called Verification. In Deductive Reasoning, 
especially when it involves elaborate calculations, there is 



AND VERIFICATION. 23I 

always great danger lest we should have omitted to take 
into account some particular agency or element, or have 
miscalculated its effects, or have formed a false estimate 
of the combined effect of the various agencies or elements 
in operation. The only remedy against these possible 
errors, besides the employment of great caution in the 
conduct of the deductive process itself, is to be found in 
Verification, a word which, in its stricter sense, appears 
to be applied to the process of testing, by means of an 
appeal to facts, the validity of the conclusions already 
arrived at by a course of deductive reasoning. Thus it 
had been deductively inferred from the Copernican 
theory that the planets Venus and Mercury ought to 
pass through phases, like the moon, and the application 
of the telescope, by means of which they were actually 
seen to assume these phases, furnished a triumphant 
verification of the inference. Every occurrence of an 
eclipse of the sun or moon or of the transit or occul- 
tation of a star, when it accords with the previous calcu- 
lations of astronomers, is also an instance of Verification 
in this, the stricter, sense of the term. But the word is 
often used in a looser sense and extended to all cases 
in which an appeal is made to facts, as, for instance, 
when we perform an experiment in order to test the truth 
of a hypothesis, or where we put in action the Method of 
Difference in order to supplement the characteristic un- 
certainty attaching to the employment of the Method of 
Agreement. Of the process denoted by this looser sense 
of the word, instances will readily occur to every one. 



^3^ RELATION OF INDUCTION TO DEDUCTION^ 

Thus, the diminution in the periods of Encke's comet has 
been regarded as a verification of the theory that space 
is filled with an interstellar medium ; or, to take an in- 
stance from a very different class of subjects, the recent 
breaking-up of the slave-system in the Southern States of 
America may be regarded as a verification of the pre- 
diction that slave and free institutions could not long 
co-exist under the same political form of government. 
For an instance of a case in which the Method of Dif- 
ference is called in to verify a previous employment of 
the Method of Agreement, we may refer back to the 
enquiry into the cause of crystallization, already adduced 
in our discussion of those two methods ^ 

There is a still wider application of the word Veri- 
fication, by which it is extended to any corroboration of 
one mode of proof by means of another. It thus in- 
cludes a deductive proof adduced in corroboration of an 
inductive one. The most common instance of this kind 
of verification is the inclusion of a partial under a 
more general law, the partial law having been arrived at 
inductively, and it being subsequently shown that the 
more general law leads deductively to it. Thus, the 
phenomena of the Tides had, prior to the epoch of 
Newton, been partially explained by the inductive me- 
thod. Newton, by deducing these phenomena from the 
Law of Universal Gravitation, not only afforded a much 
more complete explanation, but also furnished the most 
convincing verification of the results already arrived at. 

» See pp.135, 6; H7. 8. 



AND VERIFICATION. 233 

Similarly, the laws of falling bodies on the earth's sur- 
face, which had already been proved inductively, were, 
from the time of Newton, brought under the law of uni- 
versal gravitation, and proved deductively from it. The 
same was also the case with Kepler's Laws, when they 
were proved deductively from the theorem of the Central 
Force. 

It frequently happens that what may be called a re- 
sidual phenomenon affords an unexpected, and, on that 
accoimt, a striking verification of some law which is not 
immediately the object of investigation. Thus, to recur 
to an instance already adduced for another purpose, 
when it was found that the difference between the ob- 
served and calculated velocities of sound was exactly 
accounted for by the law of the development of heat by 
compression, this law acquired so novel and striking a 
confirmation as to leave no doubt of its truth or univer- 
sality. 

The following examples, both taken from Lyell's 
Principles of Geology^, will be interesting, the one as 
affording a verification, though by no means a complete 
one, of the bold theory of cosmical clouds, the other as 
presenting an instance of a very plausible theory which 
fails to receive any verification from an appeal to facts. 

• Ch. viii. (ninth edition) ; ch. xiii. (tenth edition). The fornaer passage 
appears not to be embodied in the last edition. Various other theories 
have been proposed in order to account for the appearance of temporary 
stars. See Guillemin, The Heavens, and Lardner's Handbook o/AstrO' 
nomy, third edition, edited and revised by £. Dunkin. 



^34 RELATION OF INDUCTION TO DEDUCTION^ 

* There is still another astronomical suggestion respecting 
the possible causes of secular variations in the terrestrial 
climates which deserves notice. It has long been known that 
certain stars are liable to great and periodical fluctuations in 
splendour, and Sir J. Herschel has lately ascertained (Jan. 
1840), that a large and brilliant star, called alpha Orionis, sus- 
tained, in the course of six weeks, a loss of nearly half its 
light. "This phenomenon," he remarks, "cannot fail to 
awaken attention, and revive those speculations which \rere 
first put forth by my father Sir W. Herschel, respecting the 
possibility of a change in the lustre of our sun itself. If there 
really be a community of nature between the sun and fixed 
stars, every proof that we obtain of the extensive prevalence 
of such periodical changes in those remote bodies, adds to the 
probability of finding something of the kind nearer home." 
Referring then to the possible bearing of such facts on ancient 
revolutions, in terrestrial climates, he says, that, "it is a 
matter of observed fact, that many stars have undergone, in 
past ages, within the records of astronomical history, very 
extensive changes in apparent lustre, without a change of 
distance adequate to producing such an effect. If our sun 
were even intrinsically much brighter than at present, the 
mean temperature of the surface of our globe would, of 
course, be proportionally greater. I speak now not of perio- 
dical, but of secular changes. But the argument is compli- 
cated with the consideration of the possibly imperfect 
transparency of the celestial spaces, and with the cause of 
that imperfect transparency, which may be due to material 
non-luminous particles diffused irregularly in patches analo- 
gous to nebulae, but of greater extent — to cosmical cloueLsy in 
short - of whose existence we have, I think, some indication 
in the singular and apparently capricious phenomena of tem- 
porary stars, and perhaps in the recent extraordinary sudden 
increase and hardly less sudden diminution of 17 Argus," 

'The gradual diminution of the supposed primitive heat 



AND VERIFICATION. 235 

of the globe has been resorted to by many geologists as the 
principal cause of alterations of climate. The matter of our 
planet is imagined, in accordance with the conjectures of 
Leibnitz, to have been originally in an intensely heated state, 
and to have been parting ever since with portions of its heat, 
and at the same time contracting its dimensions. There are, 
undoubtedly, good grounds for inferring from recent observa- 
tion and experiment, that the temperature of the earth in- 
creases as we descend from the surface to that slight depth 
to which man can penetrate : but there are no positive proofs 
of a secular decrease of internal heat accompanied by con- 
traction. ' On the contrary, La Place has shown, by reference 
to astronomical observations made in the time of Hipparchus, 
that in the last two thousand years at least there has been no 
sensible contraction of the globe by cooling; for had this 
been the case, even to an extremely small amount, the day 
would have been shortened, whereas its length has certainly 
not dimmished during that period by ^^th of a second.' 

In this case, however, no argument can fairly be de- 
duced from the non-verification of the theory, as the 
period of our observation, when compared with the 
enormous geological eras of which it is necessary to 
take account in these speculations, is so short as possibly 
to be infinitesimal. The theory receives no verification 
from the facts to which we appeal, but we cannot say 
that it is disproved, or even rendered improbabk, by 
their failure to support it. 

It need hardly be remarked that any verification of 
one inductive proof by another, or of an induction by 
a deduction, or of a deduction by an induction, should 
conform to the laws of deductive or inductive reasoning 



2^6 RELATION OF INDUCTION TO DEDUCTION, 

as the case may be. Verification is not a distinct mode 
of proof, but is simply a confirmation of one proof by 
another, sometimes of a deduction by an induction, 
sometimes of an induction by a deduction, and, finally, 
sometimes of one induction or deduction by another. 

The student will, of course, understand that it is not 
always necessary to employ Verification. A proof may 
be so cogent as to need no confirmation. It would be 
absurd, for instance, to appeal to actual measurement 
as a verification of the proposition enimciated in Euclid^ 
i. 47. 






CHAPTER VI. 
On the Fallacies incident to Induction. 

THE errors incidental to inductive reasoning and to 
its various subsidiary processes have already, to a great 
extent, been brought before our notice in the preceding 
chapters. In laying down the conditions essential for the 
correct conduct of a process, the mistakes which result 
from its incorrect conduct necessarily form part of our 
enquiry. Though, therefore, it may be convenient to pass 
the inductive fallacies in review, it is assumed that the 
student is already acquainted with the principal errors to 
which his processes and methods are liable. 

A. To begin with the subsidiary processes, the errors 
incident to the process of observation, or * the fallacies 
of mis-observation,' are well classified by Mr. Mill as 
those which arise from Non-observation and those which 
arise from Mal-observation. 

I. Non-observation may consist either (i) in neglect- 
ing some of the instances, or (2) in neglecting some of 
the circumstances, attendant on a given instance. 

(i) With respect to the non-observation of instances, it 



1 
.4 



2^8 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

was long ago pointed out bj Bacon ^ that there is in the 
human mind a pecuHar tendency to dwell on affirmadTe 
and to oveiiook negative instances. Familiar examples 
of this tendency will readily occur to every one. We 
think it a * curious coincidence' that we should suddenfy 
meet a man of whom we have just been talking, that 
some event should happen of which we dreamt the night 
before, or that the predictions of a fortune-teller or an 
almanac should be verified by the facts. The expLa,- 
nation of these 'curious coincidences' is that our at- 
tention is arrested by the affirmative instances, whereas 

' ' Intdlectos homanas in m qtue semd placaenmt (ant qnia recepta 
font et credita, ant quia dekctant) alia etiam omnia trahit ad sofin- 
gatiooem et consensom com illis: et licet major sit instantiamm ris 
et copia, qax occorrnnt in contrariom; tamcn eas aut non obserrat, 
ant contemnit, aut distinguendo summovet et rejicit« non sine xnagno 
et pemicioso prxjodicio, qoo prioribus iUis syllepsibns aoctoritas maneat 
iniriolata, Itaqoe recte respondit ille, qoi, com sospensa tabula in templo 
ei monstraretur eorum qui vota solverant quod naufiagii periculo elapsi 
tint, atque interrogando premeretur, anne turn quidem Deorum numeo 
agnosceret, qoxsivit denuo, " At ubi sunt illi depicti qui post vota 
noncupata perierint?'' Eadem ratio est iere omnis soperstitionis, at 
in astrologicis, in somniis, ominibos, nemesibus, et hujusmodi ; in quibos 
homines delectati hujusmodi vanitatibus advertunt eventus, ubi implentnr ; 
ast ubi fallunt, licet multo frequentius, tamen negligunt et prxterennt. 
At longe sobtilius serpit hoc malum in philosophiis et scientiis ; in quibus 
quod semel placuit reliqua (licet multo firmiora et potiora) inficit, et in 
ordinem redigit Quinetiam licet abfiierit ea, quam diximus, delectatio 
et vanitas, is tamen homano intellectui error est proprius ft perpetuus, ut 
magis moveatur et excitetur affinnativis, quam negativis; cum rite et 
ordine aequum se utrique prxbere debeat ; quin contra, in omni axiomate 
vero constituendo, major est vis instantis negative. — Novum Organum, 
Bk. I. Aph. zlvi. 



TO INDUCTION. 239 

the numberless instances in which there is no corre- 
spondence between the one set of facts and the other 
altogether escape our notice. We probably talk scores 
of times dm'ing the day of persons whom we do not 
meet immediately afterwards; we frequentiy dream in 
the most circmnstantial manner of events which never 
occur; and, where one prediction of a fortune-teller is 
verified, scores are probably falsified. The weather-pro- 
phets of the almanacs possess a considerable advantage 
in the fact that, whereas, at all times, there is at least 
a considerable chance of their predictions turning out 
true, there are certain periods, such as the equinoxes, 
at which particular kinds of weather may be anticipated 
with a probability amounting almost to certainty. 

In former generations * coincidences' of this kind were 
regarded not simply as 'curious' and 'remarkable,' but 
as proofs of some causal connection between the events. 
To talk of a person was supposed to render his presence 
more likely; a verified prediction was regarded as evi- 
dence of second- sight ; and a comet which was observed 
to be followed by a war was supposed to be, if not 
the cause of the war, at least a messenger sent from 
Heaven to proclaim its approach. The tendency to take 
note of afiirmative, and to overlook negative instances, 
is one of the causes of that hasty generalisation of which 
we shall speak in a subsequent part of this chapter ^. 

^ The following remarks of Sir John Herschel, in speaking of the verifica- 
tion of * signs of the weather/ are so apposite, that I append them in a note. 
* We would strongly recommend any of our readers whose occupations 



240 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

This tendency is considerably intensified, if the af- 
firmative instances are regarded as illustrations of some 
preconceived theory", or if the evidence afForded by 
them be supplemented by some powerful afFection of 
the mind *. It seldom happens that men can hold them- 
selves entirely indifferent with respect to two rival 
opinions and apply themselves to the comparatively un- 

lead them to attend to the '* signs of the weather," and who, from 
hearing a particular weather adage often repeated, and from noticing 
themselves a few remarkable instances of its verification, have ** begun 
to put faith in it,** to commence keeping a note-book, and to set down 
without bias all the instances which occur to them of the recognised 
antecedent, and the occurrence or non-occurrence of the expected con- 
sequent, not omitting also to set down the cases in which it is left 
undecided; and after so collecting a considerable number of instances 
(not less than a hundred), proceed to form his judgment on a fair com- 
parison of the favourable, the unfavourable, and the undecided cases : 
remembering always that the absence of a majority one way or the other 
would he in itself an improbability^ and that, therefore, to have any 
weight, the majority should be a very decided one, and that not only 
in itself, but in reference to the neutral instances. We are all involun- 
tarily much more strongly impressed by the fulfilment than by the failure 
of a prediction, and it is only when thus placing ourselves face to face 
with fact and experience, that we can fully divest ourselves of this 
bias.' — Familiar Lectures on Scientific Subjects^ Lecture IV. 

^ ' Habet enim unusquisque (praeter aberrationes naturas humanae in 
genere) specum sive cavemam quandam individuam, quae lumen naturae 

frangit et corrumpit ; vel propter differentias impressionum 

prout occurrunt in animo praeoccupato et praedisposito, aut in animo 
aequo et sedato.' — Bacon's Novum Organum^ Bk. I. Aph. xlii. 

^ * Intellectus humanus luminis sicci non est ; sed recipit infusionem a 
voluntate et affectibus ; id quod generat ad quod vult scientias : quod 
enim mavult homo verum esse, id potius credit.' — Novum Organum, 
Bk. J. Aph. xlix. 



TO INDUCTION. 24 1 

exciting task of collecting evidence impartially on either 
side. To avoid taking a side on imperfect information, 
even where our interests or passions are not directly 
concerned, is one of the last and most difficult lessons 
learned by the scientific intellect, and by ordinary men 
it is regarded as a sign of a peculiarly frigid temper- 
ament, if not of an indifference to truth. Thus, when 
the theory involved in the idea of witchcraft had once 
been conceived and accepted, and especially when it 
had led to the invention of a new crime, it came to 
be held that the burden of proof lay with those who 
called its reality in question. Every story which con- 
firmed the theory would be greedily received, while 
instances in which the supposed powers of the witch 
had failed, if noticed at all, would either leave but 
a slight impression on the mind or be easily ac- 
coimted for by supposing the intervention of a higher 
power. To the numerous class engaged in the ad- 
ministration of the laws, a not unnatural reluctance 
to question the justice of the principles on which they 
and their predecessors had been in the habit of act- 
ing would furnish an additional inducement to pass 
lightly over negative instances. Fear, or dread of 
eccentricity, would operate in the case of others ; 
and thus a theory of the most preposterous character, 
which, to a mind not preoccupied, received little or no 
confirmation from facts ^ and the truth of which could 

* When a person was convinced that he was subject to the evil 
practices of a witch, this conviction would, of course, soixifitbcEsft& "^x«c»^^'ft. 



34^ FALLACIES' INCIDENT 

easily have been brought to the test, maintained it& 
ground, and throughout many centuries continued to pro- 
duce the most mischievous results. The extent of the 
bias to which the mind, in its observation of instances is 
exposed from the influence of strong affections, is patent 
to every one. A man of a desponding temperament will 
dwell on the number of those who have failed, a man of 
a sanguine temperament on the number of those who have 
succeeded, in their respective professions. A man with 
strong sympathies will see only virtues or good traits of 
character, where one of a malevolent or critical dispo- 
sition will see only vices or blemishes. An ardent ad- 
herent of a religious sect or a political party will see 
nothing but good in those who agree with him, nothing 
but evil in those who adopt a different creed or profess 
to be guided by different principles of policy. 

Not only will a preconceived opinion or a powerful 
affection come in aid of men's natural tendency to dwell 
on affirmative and overlook negative instances, but they 
will often cause men to adhere to theories for which 
whatever may have been the history of their formation 
there is absolutely no support whatever in fact. Thus 
the theory, which prevailed down to the time of Galileo, 
that bodies fall to the earth in times inversely propor- 
tional to their weights, so that a body weighing, say, 
five pounds, would fall in a time five times as short as a 

the ill effects attributed to witchcraft itself. In other cases, some event, 
such as a death or an illness, which occurred in the ordinary course of 
nature, would confirm the suspicion. 



TO INDUCTION. 243 

body weighing one pound, rested on absolutely no evi- 
dence except the fact that, in consequence of the re- 
sistance of the air, the heavier body reaches the ground 
in a somewhat shorter time than the lighter one; still, 
till Galileo made his experiments, at the end of the 
sixteenth century, from the leaning tower of Pisa, no 
one thought of bringing to a decisive test a theory which 
it was so easy to prove or disprove. Even, without 
having recourse to experiment, one would have imagined 
that the most casual observations of fallmg bodies would 
have revealed, to a mind not strongly pre-occupied, the 
strange inaccuracy of this theory. The reception ac- 
corded to the theory that the weight of the elements 
increased in a tenfold ratio, so that earth was ten 
times heavier than water, water ten times heavier than 
air, and air ten times heavier than fire, seems still more 
astounding ^ The idea of an uniform ratio, and the 
particular ratio selected, rested solely upon fancy. 

In Sir Thomas Browne's Enquiries into Vulgar and 
Common Errors '', we have an examination of the proposi- 
tion that ' men weigh heavier dead than alive, and before 
meat than after/ Here are two extraordinary paradoxes 
which it was perfectly easy for any one to bring to a 
decisive test; and still, though an appeal to facts would 
at once have been fatal to them, they appear to have met 
with a very general reception. The grounds assigned 
for the prevalence of the latter opinion are so curious 
that they deserve to be transcribed. * ]\Iany are also of 

• Novum Organum, Bk. I. Aph. xlv. ' Bk. IV. ch. vii. 

B 2 



244 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

opinion, and some learned men maintain, that men are 
lighter after meals than before, and that by a supply 
and addition of spirits obscuring the gross ponderosity 
of the aliment ingested ; but the contrary hereof we have 
found in the trial of sundry persons in different sex and 
ages. And we conceive men may mistake, if they dis- 
tinguish not the sense of levity unto themselves, and in 
regard of the scale, or decision of trutination. For after 
a draught of wine, a man may seem lighter in himself 
from sudden refection, although he be heavier in the 
balance, from a corporal and ponderous addition; but 
a man in the morning is lighter in the scale, because 
in sleep some pounds have perspired ; and is also lighter 
unto himself, because he is refected.' It will be noticed 
that * spirits' are supposed to possess the property of 
positive levity, and that, consequently, they are regarded 
as making any body into which they enter lighter than 
it was before. The theory that certain bodies are 
positively light is itself an instance of a fallacy of 
non-observation, but, as will be seen presently, of non- 
observation of circumstances not of instances. 

Another extraordinary instance of a statement which 
obtained acceptance without any foimdation whatever m 
fact is noticed in an article in the Quarterly Review for 
January, 1865, on * Aristotle's History of Animals.' Here, 
however, there appears to be no assignable reason for the 
mistake. 

* Aristotle held some peculiar notions with respect to the 
skull. He says, " that part of the head which is covered with 



TO INDUCTION. 245 

hair is called the cranium; the fore part of this is called 
the sinciput; this is the last formed, being the last part in 
the body which becomes hard." He correctly alludes here 
to the opening in the frontal bone of a young infant, which 
gradually becomes hardened by ossification ; " the hinder part 
is the occiput, and between the occiput and sinciput is the 
crown of the head : the brain is placed beneath the sinciput, 
and the occiput is empty (!). The skull has sutures ; in women 
there is but one placed in a circle (!); men have generally 
three joined in one, and a man's skull has been seen without 
any sutures at all." The often repeated question as to how 
far Aristotle's observations are the result of his own investi- 
gation, naturally suggests itself again here ; had Aristotle ever 
dissected a human body, he never would have asserted a 
proposition so manifestly false as that the back of the head is 
empty, or that women have only one suture placed in a 
circle.* 

The passage here noticed occurs in the Historia Am- 
maimm, Bk. I. ch. vii. Cp. Bk. III. eh. vii. 

A still more remarkable instance of this description of 
fallacy is noticed in Mr. Lecky's History of European 
Morals from Augustus to Charlemagne'^, 

* Aristotle, the greatest naturalist of Greece, had observed 
that it was a curious fact, that on the sea-shore no animal 
ever dies except during the ebbing of the tide. Several cen- 
turies later, Pliny, the greatest naturalist of an empire that 
was washed by many tidal seas, directed his attention to this 
statement. He declared that after careful observations which 
had been made in Gaul, it had been found to be inaccurate, 
for what Aristotle stated of all animals, was in fact only true 
of man. It was in 1727 and the two following years, that 

• Vol. i. p. 394. 



246 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

scientific observations made at Rochefort and at Brest finally 
dissipated the delusion.* 

The influence of some strong passion or affection in 
causing men to accept theories without any support from 
observation or experiment, and often in direct defiance 
of them, may be illustrated from almost all the more 
powerful feelings of human nature. The mythologies of 
every nation are full of the wildest and most improbable 
stories, originating partly in the strength of the religious 
sentiment, partly in that love of the marvellous which 
seems to be connatural to every race of mankind, partly 
in later misinterpretations of that poetical language in 
which early races are wont to clothe their ideas. Thus, 
stories of the transformation of men into beasts, of 
rivers flowing backwards, of images falling down from 
heaven, besides other tales still more fantastic, have been 
greedily received by generation after generation in spite 
of all the analogies of nature and without one single 
instance to confirm them. The beliefs in ghosts, spirit- 
rapping, and similar phenomena, seem to have their 
origia in man's insatiable craving for the marvellous, 
acting often in combination with the feelings of fear, 
hope, or curiosity. One of the most powerful agents 
in human affairs is the passion of avarice or the insa- 
tiable desire for the accumulation of wealth. In the 
middle ages, this passion led the alchemists, contrary to 
all experience, to the belief that it was open to men to 
become suddenly and enormously rich by discovering the 
secret of transmuting other metals into gold. In modem 



TO INDUCTION. 247 

times it has frequently led, and still leads, men to embark 
in the most desperate speculations, which no scientific 
calculation of chances would justify. In a lottery, for 
instance (which is a comparatively innocuous form of 
speculation), the value of the chance is, owing to the 
expenses of management and the profit required by the 
projectors, invariably much less than the price paid for 
the ticket. But, perhaps, the most remarkable exempli- 
fication of the imreasoning desire for sudden accessions 
of wealth is to be found in the pertinacity with which, 
in spite of every warning, men would, till within the 
last few years, expend large fortimes in sinking shafts 
for coal and other minerals in strata in which the uni- 
versal experience of geologists and miners testified against 
their occurrence. In this, as in many other cases, the 
observations of competent authorities went for nothing ; 
the passion was so absorbing that it alone determined 
action. 

The fallacies due to non-observation of instances may 
be further exemplified by the tendency of the mind to 
acquiesce in the first instances which offer themselves ^ 
especially if they be of a striking kind^**, instead of care- 

® * Axiomata, quae in usu sunt, ex tenui et manipulari experientia, et 
paucis particularibus, quae ut plurimum occummt fluxere; et sunt fere 
ad mensuram eonim facta et exteusa.' — Novum Organum^ Bk. 1. 
Aph. XXV. 

'^ • Intdlectus humanus illis, quae simul et subito mentem ferire et 
subire possunt, maxime movetur; a quibus phantasia impleri et inflari 
consuevit : reliqua vero modo quodam, licet imperceptibili, ita se habere 
fingit et supponit, quomodo se habent pauca ilia quibus mens obsidetur ; 
ad ilium vero transcursum ad instaivtias Ttmo\aL% ^ \«X«to^\iK»s^ '^^-^ 



248 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

fully searching for other instances of a similar nature 
with which to compare and by means of which to in- 
terpret them. Thus, the phenomena of thunder and 
lightning would probably have received a much earlier 
explanation, had men's attention been sooner directed 
to the instances of electricity which nature presents of 
a less striking kind and on a smaller scale. Again, the 
difficulties presented to early speculators by volcanoes 
and earthquakes would have been considerably dimi- 
nished, had they been aware of the fact that there is 
hardly any portion of the earth's surface which is not 
undergoing a constant change of level by the process 
either of elevation or of subsidence, though such change 
is usually imperceptible to each single generation. The 
mistakes originating in this source of error are count- 
less. We observe certain peculiarities in some particular 
representative of a class, profession, or nation, and then 
proceed to argue as if all the members of the class, 
profession, or nation were like him. Or, a person on 
his travels in some country is unfavourably impressed 
with the hotel-keepers, porters, and carriage-drivers, and 
then proceeds to denounce the whole nation to which 
they belong, as if the characteristics of a few exceptional 
classes were the characteristics of a nationality ^^ 

quas axiomata tanquam igne probantur, tardus omnino intellectus est 
et inhabilis, nisi hoc illi per duras leges et violentum imperium im- 
ponatur.* — Novum Organum^ Bk. I. Aph. xlvii. 

^^ The history of the French language furnishes a striking instance of 
non-observation and of the curious and baseless theories to which it may 
lead : * It is well known that before certain feminine substantives, such 



TO INDUCTION. 249 

The student must have already perceived that we are 
trenching on Fallacies of Generalisation. When we 
proceed to treat insufficient evidence, or the absence of 
evidence, or popular beliefs which run counter to all 
the evidence available, as if they afforded perfectly suf- 
ficient evidence, the fallacy is one of inference, and, if 

as messe, mere, soif, faim, peur, &c., the adjective grand keeps its 
masculine tennination, grand* niesse, grand* mere , &c. Why so ? 
Grammarians, who are puzzled by nothing, tell us without hesitation 
that grand is here put for grande, and that the apostrophe marks the 
suppression of the final e. But the good sense of every scholar protests 
against this : after having learnt in childhood that e mute is cut off 
before a vowel, and never before a consonant, he is told that the e 
is here cut off without the slightest reason in such phrases as grand*- 
route, &c. The real explanation is in fact a very different one. In its 
beginning, French grammar was simply the continuation and prolonga- 
tion of Latin grammar ; consequently the Old French adjectives followed 
in all points the Latin adjective; those adjectives which had two termina- 
tions for masculine and feminine in Latin (as bonus, bona) had two in 
Old French, whereas those Latin adjectives which had but one (as grandis, 
fords, &c.), had only one in French. In the thirteenth century men 
said une grand femme, grandis femina ; une ante mortel, mortalis anima ; 
une coutume cruel, crudelis; une plaine vert, viridis planities, &c. In 
the fourteenth century the meaning of this distinction was no longer 
understood ; and men, deeming it a mere irregularity, altered the form 
of the second to that of the first class of adjectives, and wrote grande, 
verte, forte, &c., after the pattern of bonne, &c. A trace of the older 
and more correct form survives in such expressions as grand^mere, grand^- 
route, grand'faim, grand'garde, &c., which are the ddbris of the older 
language. In the seventeenth century, Vaugelas and the grammarians 
of the age, in their ignorance of the historic reason of this usage, 
pompously decreed that the form of these words arose from an euphonic 
suppression of the e mute, which must be indicated by an apostrophe.' 
— Brachet's Historical Grammar of the French Tongue, Mr. Kitchin's 
Transl., Preface, p. vi. 



250 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

the simulated inference be inductive, it is a FaUacy of 
Greneralisation. But the absence or insufficiency of the 
evidence, if due to our not having kept our minds 
sufficientiy open to facts or not having taken sufficient 
pains to collect all the facts pertinent to the question, 
is a Fallacy of Non-observation, and is a defect in the 
preliminary process rather than in the inductive in- 
ference itself. It is believed that all the instances de- 
scribed above fall imder this head, though the inferences 
founded upon them, where they possess any show^ of 
justification at all, are cases of unwarranted Inductio per 
Simplicem Enumerationem, and so afiford illustrations of 
Fallacies of Generalisation. 

(2) The second division of the Fallacies of Non-obser- 
vation is the fallacy which arises from overlooking some 
of the material circumstances attendant on a given in- 
stance. Here the defect is not in the number or per- 
tinency of the instances, but in their character; the 
description of the instances themselves is untrustworthy. 
Till we have ascertained that we are fully acquainted with 
all the material circumstances of the cases examined, we 
cannot rely upon our facts, and, consequently, we have 
no right to proceed to ground any inference upon them. 
'The circumstances/ says Sir John HerscheP^ 'which 
accompany any observed fact, are main features in its 
observation, at least until it is ascertained by sufficient 
experience what circumstances have nothing to do with 

" Herschel's Discourse on the Study of Natural Philosophy , § m. 



TO INDUCTION, 25 1 

it, and might therefore have been left unobserved without 
sacrificing the fad. In observing and recording a fact, 
therefore, altogether new, we ought not to omit any cir- 
cumstance capable of being noted, lest some one of the 
omitted circumstances should be essentially connected 
with the fact, . . . For instance, in the fall of meteoric 
stones, flashes of fire are seen proceeding from a cloud, 
and a loud rattling noise like thunder is heard. These 
circumstances, and the sudden stroke and destruction 
ensuing, long caused them to be confoimded with an 
effect of lightning, and called thunderbolts. But one 
circumstance is enough to mark the difference : the flash 
and sound have been perceived occasionally to emanate 
from a very small cloud insulated in a clear sky; a com- 
bination of circumstances which never happens in a 
thimder storm, but which is undoubtedly intimately con- 
nected with their real origin/ 

The extreme difficulty of obtaining, by means of the 
thermometer, a correct measure of the temperature of 
the atmosphere, owing to the conduction of heat by the 
stand and its radiation from surrounding objects, together 
with the errors constantly made by observers from not 
sufficiently providing against, or allowing for, these 
sources of interference, will serve to every one as a 
familiar illustration of the great importance of the caution 
which it is here intended to furnish. 

The following examples, adduced by Mr. MilP', are 

" System 0/ Logic, Bk. V. ch, iv, % i^. 



2^2 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

50 interesting and appropriate, that I take the liberty 
of transcribing them :— 

* Such, for instance [namely the imperfect observation of 
particular facts], was one of the mistakes committed in the 
celebrated phlogistic theory ; a doctrine which accounted for 
combustion by the extrication of a substance called phlogiston, 
supposed to be contained in all combustible matter. The 
hypothesis accorded tolerably well with superficial appear- 
ances ; the ascent of flame naturally suggests the escape of 
a substance; and the visible residuum of ashes, in bulk and 
weight, generally falls extremely short of the combustible 
material. The error was, non-observation of an important 
portion of the actual residue, namely, the gaseous products 
of combustion. When these were at last noticed and brought 
into account, it appeared to be an universal law, that all 
substances gain instead of losing weight by undergoing com- 
bustion ; and, after the usual attempt to accommodate the old 
theory to the new fact by means of an arbitrary hypothesis 
(that phlogiston had the quality of positive levity instead of 
gravity), chemists were conducted to the true explanation, 
namely, that instead of a substance separated, there was on 
the contrary a substance absorbed. 

* Many of the absurd practices which have been deemed 
to possess medicinal efficacy, have been indebted for their 
reputation to non-observance of some accompanying circum- 
stance which was the real agent in the cures ascribed to them. 
Thus, of the sympathetic powder of Sir Kenelm Digby: 
" Whenever any wound had been inflicted, this powder was 
applied to the weapon that had inflicted it, which was, more- 
over, covered with ointment, and dressed two or three times 
a day. The wound itself, in the meantime, was directed 
to be brought together, and carefully bound up with clean 
linen rags, but above allf to be let alone for seven days, at the 
end of which period the bandages were removed, when the 



TO INDUCTION. 253 

wound- was generally found perfectly united. The triumph 
of the cure was decreed to the mysterious agency of the 
sympathetic powder which had been so assiduously applied 
to the weapon, whereas it is hardly necessary to observe that 
the promptness of the cure depended upon the total ex- 
clusion of air from the wound, and upon the sanative opera- 
tions of nature not having received any disturbance from the 
officious interference of art. The result, beyond all doubt, 
furnished the first hint which led surgeons to the improved 
practice of healing wounds by what is technically called the 

The next example I extract from Bp. Wilkins' very 
curious tractate, entitled A Discovery of a New World, 
or a Discourse tending to prove that *tis probable there may 
be another Habitable World in the Moon : — 

* He [that is, * a late reverend and learned Bishop,' 
writing * under the feigned name of Domingo Gonsales*^] 
supposeth that there is a natural and usual passage for many 
creatures betwixt our earth and this planet. Thus, he says, 
those great multitude of locusts wherewith divers countries 
have been destroyed, do proceed from thence. And if we 
peruse the authors who treat of them, we shall find that many 
times they fly in numberless troops or swarms, and for sundry 
days together before they fall are seen over those places in 
great high clouds, such as coming nearer, are of extension 
enough to obscure the day, and hinder the light of the sun. 
From which, together with divers other such relations, he 
concludes that *tis not altogether improbable they should 

" Dr. Paris* Pbarmacologia, pp. 23-24. 

^' The small tract here referred to is republished in vol. viii. of the 
Harleian Miscellanies (Park's Edition). The author was Francis 
Godwin, afterwards Bishop of Hereford, and author of the Vell-known 
book De Prcesulibus Anglice Commentarius, 



aS4 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

proceed from the moon. Thus, likewise, he supposes the 
swallows, cuckoos, nightingales, with divers other fowl, which 
are with us only half a year, to fly up thither when they go 
from us. Amongst which kind, there is a wild swan in the 
East Indies, which at certain seasons of the year do constantly 
take their flight thither. Now, this bird being of a great 
strength, able to continue for a long flight, as also going 
usually in flocks like our wild geese, he supposeth that 
many of them together might be thought to carry the weight 
of a man; especially if an engine were so contrived (as he 
thinks it might) that each of them should bear an equal share 
in the burden. So that by this means, 'tis easily conceivable, 
how once a year a man might finish such voyage ; going along 
with these birds at the beginning of winter, and again return- 
ing with them at the spring ^^' 

A more accurate and extended series of observations 
would, of course, have shewn that the birds and locusts 
migrated from other parts of the earth's surface. 

It is not necessary to multiply examples of the errors 
arising from slovenliness and inattention in the collec- 
tion or examination of our instances. The necessity of 
maintaining the strictest caution and accuracy in the 
conduct of our observations and experiments has already 
been insisted upon in the Second Chapter of this work. 

II. Besides the errors which originate in the neglect of 
instances or of some of the circumstances which are con- 
nected with a given instance, there is another class of 
errors derived from mistaking for observation that which 
is not observation at all, but inference. To this class of 

" Wilklns* Discovery of a New World, Fifth Edition, p. i6o. 



TO INDUCTION. 2^5 

errors Mr. Mill gives the name of Fallacies of Mal- 
Observation. That which is strictly matter of observa- 
tion or perception does not admit of being called in 
question; it is the ultimate basis of all our reasoning, 
and, if we are to repose any confidence whatever in the 
exercise of our faculties, must be taken for granted. But 
there are few of our perceptions, even of those which to 
the unphilosophical observer appear to be the simplest, 
which are not inextricably blended with inference. Thus, 
as is well known to every student of psychology, in what 
are familiarly called the perceptions of distance and of 
form, the only perception proper is that of the various 
tints of colour reflected on the retina of the eye, and it is 
by a combination of this with perceptions of touch that the 
mind gains its power of determining form and distance. 
Now a judgment of this kind, which is really due to in- 
ference, is, especially by the uneducated and unreflecting, 
perpetually mistaken for that which is due to direct ob- 
servation ; and thus what is really only an inference from 
facts is often emphatically asserted to be itself a matter of 
fact. *In proportion,' says Mr. Mill", *to any person's 
deficiency of knowledge and mental cultivation, is gene- 
rally his inability to discriminate between his inferences 
and the perceptions on which they were grounded. Many 
a marvellous tale, many a scandalous anecdote, owes its 
origin to this incapacity. The narrator relates, not what 
he saw or heard, but the impression which he derived 

" MiU's Logic, Bk. V. ch. iv. § 5, 



256 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

from what he saw or heard, and of which perhaps the 
greater part consisted of inference, though the whole is 
related not as inference but as matter-of-fact. The diffi- 
culty of inducing witnesses to restrain within any mode- 
rate limits the intermixture of their inferences with the 
narrative of their perceptions, is well known to experi- 
enced cross-examiners; and still more is this the case 
when ignorant persons attempt to describe any natural 
phenomenon. " The simplest narrative," says Dugald 
Stewart, "of the most illiterate observer involves more 
or less of hypothesis; nay, in general, it will be found 
that, in proportion to his ignorance, the greater is the 
number of conjectural principles involved in his state- 
ments. A village apothecary (and, if possible, in a still 
greater degree, an experienced nurse) is seldom able to 
describe the plainest case, without employing a phrase- 
ology of which every word is a theory : whereas a simple 
and genuine specification of the phenomena which mark 
a particular disease; a specification unsophisticated by 
fancy, or by preconceived opinions, may be regarded as 
unequivocal evidence of a mind trained by long and 
successful study to the most difiicult of all arts, that of 
the faithful inierpretation of nature.'" 

No better instance can be given of the Fallacy of 
Mal-Observation than that adduced by Mr. Mill and 
many other authors of the confusion between observation 
and inference, namely, what was called the common-sense 
argument against the truth of the Copernican System. 
That the earth should move round the sun, men said, was 



TO INDUCTION. 257 

impossible ; for, every day, they saw the sun rise and set 
and perform his course in the heavens. They felt the earth 
at rest, they saw the sun in motion, and it was absurd to 
call upon them to disbelieve the direct evidence of their 
senses. It need hardly be said that what they mistook 
for the direct evidence of their senses was really an in- 
ference. What they saw was consistent with one or 
other of two hypotheses, that the sun moved round the 
earth, or that the earth moved round the sun; and, 
neglecting to take any accoimt of the latter, they assumed 
the former. If it were not for the impressions of a con- 
trary kind derived from the actual motion of the car- 
riage, a man, whirled along in a railway train, might 
with equal justice maintain, by an appeal to the evidence 
of his eyesight, that the trees and the houses were run- 
ning past him. 

Ventriloquism supplies another familiar instance of the 
same error. A man who had never before been imposed 
upon by the tricks of a ventriloquist, and who was not 
aware of the character of the deception, would be positive 
in maintaining that he had the direct evidence of the 
sense of hearing in support of his belief that the sound 
he heard proceeded from a particular person or a par- 
ticular part of the building other than that from which it 
really did. The fact, of course, is that the sound itself is 
all that is directly perceived by the sense of hearing ; the 
reference of it to a particular person or a particular place 
is an act of inference grounded upon constant, or at 
least frequent, association. What is do\\fc \s^ '^'^ ^^sv- 



258 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

triloquist is not to deceive the sense of hearing, but to 
mislead the faculty of judgment. 

What are called 'delusions' and 'hallucinations' fur- 
nish a further instance of Mal-observation. It seems to 
be now pretty generally agreed that these are due to 
morbid affections of the sensory ganglia. ' The patient's 
senses,' says Dr. Maudsley^®, speaking of what he calls 
sensorial insanity y ' are possessed with hallucinations, their 
ganglionic central cells being in a state of convulsive 
action ; before the eyes are blood-red flames of fire, amidst 
which whosoever happens to present himself, appears as 
a devil, or otherwise horribly transformed ; the ears are 
filled with a terrible roaring noise, or resound with a voice 
imperatively commanding him to save himself; the smell 
is perhaps one of sulphurous stifling ; and the desperate 
and violent actions are, like the furious acts of the ele- 
phant, the convulsive re-actions to such fearful halluci- 
nations. The individual in such a state is a machine set 
in destructive motion, and he perpetrates the extremest 
violence or the most desperate murder without conscious- 
ness at the time, and without memory of it afterwards.' 
What is here said of delusions in that extreme form in 
which they assume unmistakeably the character of mad- 
ness applies equally, as an explanation, to those less 
obtrusive, though far more frequent, forms in which they 
produce semi-insanity, monomania, melancholy, or par- 
tial and temporary deception. In all these cases, the 
sensations are really experienced; the error consists in 

" Maudsley, The Physiology and Pathology ofMind, ch. iv. p. loi. 



TO INDUCTION. 259 

referring the cause of the sensations to external objects 
rather than to the morbid condition or action of the 
brain itself. The testimony of others, or the inherent 
improbability of the things perceived, ought to be re- 
garded, though they seldom are, as sufficient proof that 
the evidence of the senses is given under abnormal and 
untrustworthy conditions. 

The description here given of the errors originating 
in Non-observation or Mal-observation includes, as will 
already have been perceived, the errors incident to arti- 
ficial as well as to natural observation, that is, to experi- 
ment as well as to observation proper. 

III. The errors incidental to the other operations 
preliminary to induction, namely, classification, nomen- 
clature, terminology, and hypothesis, will be sufiiciently 
apparent on a perusal of the sections appropriated to 
the discussion of those processes. In the steps inter- 
mediate between the observation of individual facts and 
the inductive inference itself, it is in the employment 
of artificial instead of natural classifications, and in 
the neglect of the rules designed to guard against the 
formation of illegitimate hypotheses, that the danger of 
error mainly Ues. 

B. The fallacies incidental to the performance of the in- 
ductive process itself may be called Fallacies of General- 
isation. An error of this class is committed whenever, 
in arguments grounded on experience, we overrate the 
value of the evidence before us; that is, whenever we 

s 2 



26o FALLACIES INCIDENT 

accept an imperfect induction as a perfect one, or when- 
ever, in an induction confessedly imperfect, we under- 
estimate the amount of imperfection. 

Of the imperfect inductions, the argument from analogy 
is little likely to be mistaken for a perfect induction. The 
strength of the analogy is often grossly exaggerated, and 
an argument which possesses little or no probability is 
often adduced as afifording highly probable evidence; but, 
as this kind of argument is very seldom^* treated as 
affording absolute certainty, the discussion of false ana- 
logies may be reserved till we have completed the treat- 
ment of those errors which consist in regarding imperfect 
as perfect inductions. 

Excluding analogy, there are, as we have seen, two 
forms of imperfect induction, that which employs the 
incomplete Inductio per Simplicem Enumerationem and 
that which consists in an imperfect fulfilment of the 
conditions of the inductive methods. An argument of 
either of these classes may be, and frequently is, mis- 
taken for a perfect induction. We shall first notice the 
case in which scientific induction is simulated by the 
incomplete Inductio per Simplicem Enimierationem. 

IV. When men first begin to argue from their experience 
of the past to their expectation of the future, or from 
the observation of what immediately surrounds them to 
the properties of distant objects, they seem naturally to 

^ The geological example on p. 219 may perhaps be an instance of 
an analogical argument thus regarded. Many writers have certainly 
treated the inference as if its certainty admitted of no doubt. 



TO INDUCTION. 26 1 

fall into this unscientific and unreflective mode of rea- 
soning. They have constantly seen two phenomena in 
conjmiction, and, consequently, they cannot imagine them 
to be dissevered, or they have never seen two phenomena 
in conjunction, and, consequently, they cannot imagine 
them to be associated. The difficulties experienced by 
children in accommodating their conceptions to the 
wider experiences of men ; the tendency of the unin- 
structed, and frequently even of the instructed, to invest 
with the peculiar circumstances of their own time or 
country the men of a former generation or of another 
land ; the prejudices entertained against those of another 
creed, or party, or nationality, as if moral excellence 
were never dissociated from particular opinions or a 
particular lineage, — ^are all evidences of the limited 
character of our first efi*orts at generalisation. It is 
long before men learn to discriminate between the 
material and immaterial circumstances attendant on 
any given phenomenon, to perceive the irrelevancy of 
the immaterial circumstances, and to recognise the 
necessity of insisting on a repetition of all the mate- 
rial circumstances before they can anticipate a similar 
effect. But not only is the Inductio per Simplicem 
Enumerationem the mode of generalisation natural to 
immature and uninstructed minds; it is the method 
which, till the time of Bacon '^, or at least till the era 

^ Bacon seems to be never weary of condemning this unscientific 
procedure. Thus, in addition to the aphorism already quoted (p. 1 1 7)t 
we have, amongst others, the following em^baAxc '^'&^<^« 5" K»ssa!a^». 



262 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

of those great discoveries which shortly preceded the 
time of Bacon, was almost universal. Aristotle, it is 
true, requires that an induction should be based on an 
examination of all the instances; but this requirement 
being in the vast majority of cases impossible of ful- 
filment, he was obliged, whenever he had recourse to 
experience, to content himself with an inspection of 
those cases which were nearest at hand. Thus, in the 
very passage^ in which he emphatically asserts that the 
minor premiss of the inductive syllogism (for he repre- 
sents induction under the syllogistic form) should include 
all the instances, he argues that all animals which are 
deficient in bile are long-lived, because he finds this to 

qusB in usu sunt, ex tenoi et manipulari experientia, et paucis particulari- 
bus, qux ut plurimum occumint, fluxere; et sunt fere ad mensuram 
eorum facta et extensa : ut nil minim sit, si ad nova particularia non 
ducant. Quod si forte instantia aliqua, non prius animadversa aut 
cognita, se offerat, axioma distinctione aliqua frivola salvatur, ubi emen- 
dari ipsum verius foret/ Nov. Org. Bk. I. Aph. xxv. * At philosophiae 
genus empiricum placita magis deformia et monstrosa educit, qnam 
sopbisticum aut rationale genus; quia non in luce notionum vulgarinm 
(qusB licet tenuis sit et superficialis, tamen est quodammodo universalis, 
et ad multa pertinens) sed in paucorum experimentorum angustiis et 

obscuritate fiindatum est Sed tamen circa hujusmodi philosophias 

cautio nullo modo praetermittenda erat ; quia mente jam prxvidemus et 
auguramur, si quando homines, nostris monitis excitati, ad experientiam 
se serio contulerint (valere jussis doctrinis sophisticis) turn demum, propter 
praematuram et praeproperam intellectus festinationem et saltum sive 
volatum ad generalia et rerum principia, fore ut magnum ab hujusmodi 
philosophiis periculum immineat ; cui malo etiam nunc obviam ire debe- 
mus.* Aph. Ixiv. 
^ Analytica Priora^ ii. 23. 



TO INDUCTION, 263 

be the case with the man, the horse, and the mule. 
Aristotle's works, and especially those on Natural His- 
tory, abound in rash generalisations of this kind. *It 
is a fact,' says Mr. Lewes ^^, *that normally in turtles, 
and exceptionally in elephants, horses, and oxen, there 
is an ossification of the septimi of the heart. Aristotle 
saw or heard of one of these "bones" in the hearts of 
a horse and an ox, and forthwith generalised the obser- 
vation thus : " The heart is destitute of bones except in 
horses and in a species of ox ; these, however, in con- 
sequence of their size, have something bony as a support, 
just as we find throughout the whole body^." His 
Spanish follower Funes Y Mendo9a improves on this 
by saying that the bone acts like a stick to support 
the weight of the heart, which is very great.' 

There is another passage in which Aristotle tells us 
that the cranium of a dog consists of a single bone^. 
* It is probable,' says the author of the review previously 
quoted^', *that Aristotle had got hold of the cranium 
of an old individual in which the sutures had become 
obliterated.' 

The employment of the Inductio per Simplicem Enu- 
merationem prevailed so universally from the time of 
Aristotle to the rise of modem science that it seems 

^ Lewes* Aristotle^ ch. xvi. § 399. 
^ De Partihus Animalium, Bk. III. ch. iv. 

** rd filv ydtp Ix** fiovdffrtov rd Kpaviov, &a'ntp 6 icuow^ ra h\ ffvy- 
K€ifi«voVt &<Tir(p ayOpomot. Hiitoria Animaliumy Bk. III. ch. vii. 
* Quarterly Review^ No. 233, Art. ii. 



264 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

unnecessary to multiply instances of it during that period. 
But it may be instructive to illustrate from the history 
of more modern times the peculiar facility with which 
some even of the greatest discoverers have lapsed into 
this erroneous form of reasoning. 

'Bichat,' says Mr. Lewes^^, 'tried to establish a gene- 
ralisation which has been much admired, namely, that all the 
organs of Animal life are double and symmetrical, while all 
the organs of Vegetal life are single and asymmetrical. Un- 
happily the facts do not fit. In the commencement almost 
e^ery organ is double and symmetrical ; and only in the later 
stages of development do the difierences appear. Even in the 
matured organism we find many striking exceptions to Bichat's 
generalisation. Thus the parotid, sublingual, and mammary 
glands, the lungs, the kidneys, ovaries and testes, are all 
vegetal organs, and all generally double. And if the heart 
and uterus are classed as single organs, then must the brain 
and spinal cord be classed thus. While in birds the liver is 
double and symmetrical.* 

*It is in a great degree true,* we are informed by Dr, 
Paris'", * that the sensible qualities of plants, such as colour 
taste, and smell, have an intimate relation to their properties, 
and may often lead by analogy to an indication of their 
powers ; we have an example of this in the dark and gloomy 
aspect of the Luridce, which is indicative of their narcotic and 
very dangerous qualities, as Datura, Hyoscyamus, Atropa^ and 
Nicotiana, Colour is certainly in many cases a test of activity • 
the deepest of coloured flowers, the Digitalis, for example 
are the most active, and when the leaves of powerful plants 
lose their green hue, we may conclude that a corresponding 

2« Lewes* Aristotle, ch. xvi. § 399 d. 

^ Pbarmacologia, ninth cd. fp. no, in. 



TO INDUCTION. 26^ 

deterioration has taken place with respect to their virtues; 
but Linnaeus ascribed too much importance to such an indica- 
tion, and his aphorisms are unsupported by facts; for in- 
stance, he says, ''Color pallidus iruipidum, viridis crudum, 
luteus amarumy ruber acidumy albus dulce, niger ingratum, 
indicat."' 

The early history of Geology presents, in the con- 
troversy which was long carried on between the Nep- 
tunians and Vulcanians, a remarkable instance of the 
errors arising from a partial induction, as well as of the 
tenacity with which men will cling to views to which they 
have once, committed themselves. The Neptmiians, the 
student need hardly be told, referred all geological phe- 
nomena to the influence of water, while the Vulcanians 
greatly exaggerated the action of heat in the past his- 
tory pf the globe, and the number of formations to be 
ascribed to an igneous origin. Of the Neptunians, the 
great Saxon geologist Werner was the chief. 

* Werner,* says Sir Charles Lyell ^*, * had not travelled to 
distant countries; he had merely explored a small portion 
of Germany, and conceived, and persuaded others to believe, 
that the whole surface of our planet, and all the mountain 
chains in the world, were made after the model of his own 
province. It became a ruling object of ambition in the minds 
of his pupils to confirm the generalisations of their great 
master, and to discover in the most distant parts of the globe 
his " universal formations," which he supposed had been each 
in succession simultaneously precipitated over the whole earth 
from a common menstruum or "chaotic fluid." It now 
appears that the Saxon professor had misinterpreted many 

* Lyell's Principles 0/ Geology ^ Bk, I, cVu v»i « 



266 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

of the most important appearances even in the immediate 
neighbourhood of Freyberg. Thus, for example, within a 
day's journey of his school, the porphyry, called by him 
primitive, has been found not only to send forth veins or 
dikes through strata of the coal formation, but to overlie 
them in mass/ 

* In regard to basalt and other igneous rocks, Werner's 
theory was original, but it was also extremely erroneous. 
The basalts of Saxony and Hesse, to which his observations 
were chiefly confined, consisted of tabular masses capping the 
hills, and not connected with the levels of existing valleys, 
like many in Auvergne and the Vivarais. These basalts, SaA 
all other rocks of the same family in other countries, were, 
according to him, chemical precipitates from water. He 
denied that they were the products of submarine volcanoes ; 
and even taught that, in the primeval ages of the world, there 
were no volcanoes.* 

After describing the complete demolition of this theory 
by some of Werner's contemporaries, Sir Charles Lyell 
adds : — 

'Notwithstanding this mass of evidence, the scholars of 
Werner were prepared to support iiis opinions to their utmost 
extent ; maintaining, in the fulness of their faith, that even 
obsidian was an aqueous precipitate. As they were blinded 
by their veneration for the great teacher, they were impatient 
of opposition, and soon imbibed the spirit of a faction ; and 
their opponents, the Vulcanists, were not long in becoming 
contaminated with the same intemperate zeal. Ridicule and 
irony were weapons more frequently employed than argument 
by the rival sects, till at last the controversy was carried on 
with a degree of bitterness almost unprecedented in questions 
of physical science. Desmarest alone, who had long before 
provided ample materials for refuting such a theory, kept 



TO INDUCTION, 267 

aloof from the strife; and whenever a zealous Neptunist 
wished to draw the old man into an argument, he was satisfied 
with replying " Go and see." ' 

It is remarked by Mr. Mill that the Method of Simple 
Enmneration, though almost banished from the physical 
sciences, is still the common and received method of 
induction in whatever relates to man and society. The 
reason of this is to be sought in the extraordinary dif- 
ficulty of subjecting this class of speculations to the 
more scientific methods. Moral and social phenomena 
are so complex that it is often next to impossible 
to discover by elimination the true connection between 
any two events or sets of facts. Take, for instance, such 
questions as the influence of any particular form of 
government upon the welfare of the people among whom 
it is established, the effects of religion, or of any particular 
form of religion, upon morals, the social and political 
conditions most favourable to the development of art, 
or literature, or science, or commerce. Here, if it be 
required to discover the cause of a given effect, there are 
given a set of consequents constantly varying in their 
character and intensity, and a set of antecedents, often 
very numerous, any one of which may have an appreci- 
able influence in the production of the effect in ques- 
tion ; and it is obvious that to detect the precise degree 
in which the effect is due to any one of these antecedents, 
even supposing the task to be possible, will require the 
utmost skill, patience, and dispassionateness in the 
selection and comparison of instances. Nor, if it be 



268 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

required to discover the effect of a given cause, will the 
task be much simplified; for, though it may be possible 
to fix the precise time at which a new cause — say a new 
form of religion, a new form of government, or a new 
commercial tariff — was introduced, yet, before it can be 
argued that any novel event which may appear to have 
resulted from it, is really due to it, as an effect to a cause, 
the enquirer is bound to satisfy himself (i) that the intro- 
duction of the new cause was not accompanied by other 
causes which may have wholly or partially produced the 
supposed effect, (2) that the new cause and the supposed 
effect are not joint effects of some common cause which 
he may have overlooked. It is the extreme difficulty of 
bringing this class of questions within the requirements 
of scientific induction, that has led, on the one hand, to 
the employment of the loose Method of Inductio per 
Simplicem Enumerationem, or of a mere appeal to un- 
sifted experience, and on the other to the disbelief in the 
possibility of arriving at any satisfactory conclusions upon 
them. At the ' same time, there can be little doubt that 
moral and social enquiries are beginning to emerge from 
the chaotic state of confusion in which they have hitherto 
been sunk, and that what are now dignified with the titles 
of the moral and political sciences, however imperfect 
they may be, are beginning to be something more than 
mere collections of random guesses, or conclusions drawn 
from the first undisciplined impressions of the teaching of 
experience. 

To the class of fallacies originating in the employment 



TO INDUCTION. 269 

of the incomplete Inductio per Simplicem Enumerationem 
may perhaps be referred the illegithnate use of the Argu- 
ment from Authority. The opinions or predictions of a 
certain man or of a certain class of men upon some parti- 
cular question or questions have been subsequently found 
to be verified by the issue of events or an examination of 
the facts. From this it is sufficiently rash to infer, without 
further warrant, that the correspondence between these 
predictions or opinions and the subsequent events or 
ascertained facts is the result of knowledge, and not of 
what we call accident; but, not content even with this, 
men are apt to draw the far more unwarrantable in- 
ference that this person or class of persons is to be 
accepted as an authority on all matters, or at least on 
all matters of the same or of an analogous kind. It is 
on this principle that a savage, or even an uneducated man 
in a civilised commimity, will trust implicitly any person 
for whom he has conceived a general respect. In nine 
cases out of ten he probably acts more wisely in trust- 
ing to such a person than in trusting to himself. But 
the same habit of mind, which is a virtue among un- 
educated men and in primitive states of society, be- 
comes one of the most serious obstacles to progress 
and knowledge when men, either individually or col- 
lectively, have attained that stage at which they are 
able to enquire for themselves. We have to learn not 
only that men are to be trusted exclusively within the 
limits of their own experience, in their own profession 
or pursuit, but that even within those Iixx\Lt<& ^^ •ia^- 



ajO FALLACIES INCIDENT 

thority is apt to become tyrannical and irrational unless 
it is constantly confronted with facts and subjected to 
the criticism of others. 

But an imdiscriminating submission to the authority of 
contemporaries, of which we have hitherto exclusively 
spoken, has been but a slight source of error when com- 
pared with undiscriminating submission to the authority of 
past generations^. The latter involves a kind of com- 
pound fallacy. The authority of an Aristotle or a Galen 
has come, by the process already described, to be re- 
ceived without question and without limit by his own or 
by the succeeding generation; and then, by the con- 
stant repetition of a similar process, it is received from 
that generation by the leading minds of the next, from 
them by their contemporaries, and so on, respect for 
tradition being blended with respect for a great name, 
and both these resting for their support on the de- 
ference paid to established authority. Many of the 
propositions accepted without the slightest hesitation 
by previous generations on this kind of authority now 

^ Of this tendency we have many * glaring instances/ as Bacon would 
call them. The error has been, so to say, canonised in the proverb 
*Mallem cum Platone errare.' There is a characteristic anecdote of 
Scheiner, who contests with Galileo the honour of having been the first 
to observe the spots in the sun. * Scheiner was a monk; and, on com- 
municating to the superior of his order the account of the spots, received 
in reply from that learned father a solemn admonition against such 
heretical notions : — " I have searched through Aristotle,** he said, ** and 
can find nothing of the kind mentioned : be assured, therefore, that it 
is A deception of your senses, or of your glasses."* Baden PoweH'i 
0/ Natural Pbilosopby, p. 171. 




TO INDUCTION. 27 1 

appear to us patently absurd, nor is it without effort 
that we can realise the universality of their former re- 
ception^. Instances of such propositions have already 
been given under the head of the Fallacies of Non- 
Observation, to the production of which the undue de- 
votion to authority has, perhaps, contributed more than 
any other cause ^^. But in subjects lying remote from 

** The increasing unwillingness of men to accept a proposition on 
mere authority is thus forcibly put by Bentham, Booh of Fallacies^ 
Part I. ch. i., first published, in French by M. Dumont, in 1815, and in 
English by * A Friend/ in 1824. 

* As the world grows older, if at the same time it grows wiser (which 
it will do, unless the period shall have arrived at which experience, the 
mother of wisdom, shall have become barren), the influence of authority 
will in each situation, and particularly in parliament, become less and less/ 

* Take any part of the field of moral science, private morality, consti- 
tutional law, private law; go back a few centuries, and you will find 
argument consisting of reference to authority, not exclusively, but in as 
large a proportion as possible. As experience has increased, authority 
has been gradually set aside, and reasoning, drawn from facts, and guided 
by reference to the end in view, true or false, has taken its place. 

****** 

* In mechanics, in astronomy, in mathematics, in the new-bom science 
of chemistry — no one has at this time of day either effrontery or folly 
enough to avow, or so much as to insinuate, that the most desirable state 
of these branches of useful knowledge, the most rational and eligible 
course, is to substitute decision on the ground of authority to decision 
on the ground of direct and specific evidence.* 

^ It might appear that the illegitimate use of the Argument from 
Authority should be classed amongst the Fallacies of Non-Observation, 
but, though a blind devotion to authority is one of the most powerful 
influences in leading men to neglect observation and experiment, the dis- 
position to bow thus unduly to it is itself a fact which requires explana- 
tion, and one which it is here attempted to explain. 



2T2 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

ordinary observation, propositions almost equally absurd 
have held tiieir ground till quite recently ; some continue 
to maintain themselves, and others no doubt will be 
propounded to take advantage of the credulity of man- 
kind. 

*To give a general currency,* says Dr. Paris ^, *to a hypo- 
thetical opinion, or medicinal reputation to an inert substance, 
nothing more is required than the talismanic aid of a few 
great names ; when once established upon such a basis, inge- 
nuity, argument, and even experiment, may open their inef- 
fectual batteries ; the laconic sentiment of the Roman satirist 
is ever opposed to remonstrance : — " Marcus dixit f ita est,** 
A physician cannot err in the opinion of the public, if he 
implicitiy obeys the dogmas of authority. In the most bar- 
barous ages of ancient Egypt, he was punished or rewarded 
according to the extent of his success; but to escape the 
former it was only necessary to show that an orthodox plan 
of cure had been followed, such as was prescribed in the 
acknowledged writings of liermes. It is an instinct in our 
nature to follow the track pointed out by a few leaders* 
we are gregarious animals, in a moral as well as a physical 
sense, and we are addicted to routine because it is always 
easier to follow the opinions of others than to reason and 
judge for ourselves ; and thus do one half of the world live 
as alms-folks on the opinions of the other half. What but 
such a temper could have upheld the preposterous system of 
Galen for more than thirteen centuries, and have enabled 
it to give universal laws in medicine to Europe, Africa, and 
part of Asia ? What, but the spell of authority, could have 
inspired a general belief that the sooty washings of resin could 
act as a universal remedy ? What, but a blind devotion to 
authority, or an insuperable attachment to established custom 



32 



Dr. Paris' Pbarmacologia, Introduction, p. 76, &c. 



TO INDUCTION. 273 

and routine, could have so long preserved from oblivion the 
absurd medicines which abound in our earlier dispensatories ? 
for example, the '^ Decoctum ad Ictericoj*' of the Edinburgh 
College, which never had any foundation but that of the 
doctrine of signatures in favour of the Curcuma and CMi- 
donium majus ; and it is only within a few years that the 
Iheriaca Andromacbi^ in its ancient form, has been dismissed 
from our Pharmacopoeia. The Codex Medicamentarius 
of Paris still cherishes the many-headed monster of phar- 
macy, under the appropriate title of ^^ Ekctuarium Opiatum 
Polupbarmacum^ 



»>» 



* The same devotion to authority which induces us to re- 
tain an accustomed remedy with pertinacity, will frequently 
oppose the introduction of a novel practice with asperity, 
unless indeed it be supported by authority of still greater 
weight and consideration. The history of various articles 
of diet and medicine will prove in a striking manner how 
greatly their reputation and fate have depended upon 
authority. It was not until many years after Ipecacuan 
had been imported into Europe, that Helvetius, under the 
patronage of Louis XIV, succeeded in introducing it into 
practice: and to the eulogy of Katharine, queen of Charles 
II, we are indebted for the general introduction of tea into 
England.* 

*The history of the warm bath presents us with another 
curious instance of the vicissitudes to which the reputation 
of our valuable resources is so universally exposed; that 
which for so many ages was esteemed the greatest luxury 
in health, and the most efficacious remedy in disease, fell into 
total disrepute in the reign of Augustus, for no other reason 
than because Antonius Musa had cured the emperor of a 
dangerous malady by the use of the cold bath. The most 
frigid water that could be procured was, in consequence, 

T 



274 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

recommended on every occasion : thus Horace, in his epistle 

to Vala, exclaims — 

** Caput ac stomachum supponere fontibns audent 
Qusinis, Gabiosque petunt, et frigida rura." — Epist. xv. lib. i. 

* This practice, however, was doomed but to an ephemeral 
popularity, for although it had restored the emperor to health, 
it shortly afterwards killed his nephew and son-in-law, Mar- 
cellus ; an event which at once deprived the remedy of its 
credit and the physician of his popularity. 

*The history of the Peruvian bark would furnish a very 
curious illustration of the overbearing influence of authority 
in giving celebrity to a medicine, or in depriving it of that 
reputation to which its virtues entitle it. This heroic remedy 
was first brought to Spain in the year 1632, and we learn 
from Villerobel that it remained for seven years in that 
country before any trial was made of its powers, a certain 
ecclesiastic of Alcala being the first person in Spain to whom 
it was administered in the year 1639 ; but even at this period 
its use was limited, and it would have sunk into oblivion but 
for the supreme power of the Roman church, by whose 
auspices it was enabled to gain a temporary triumph over 
the passions and prejudices which opposed its introduction. 
Innocent the Tenth, at the intercession of Cardinal de Lugo, 
who was formerly a Spanish Jesuit, ordered that the nature 
and effects of it should be duly examined, and upon being 
reported as both innocent and salutary, it immediately rose 
into public notice ; its career, however, was suddenly stopped 
by its having unfortunately failed, in the autumn of 1652, to 
cure Leopold, Archduke of Austria, of a quartan intermittent; 
this disappointment kindled the resentment of the prince's 
principal physician, Chifletius, who published a violent philippic 
against the virtues of Peruvian bark, which so fomented the 
prejudices against its use, that it had nearly fallen into total 
neglect and disrepute.* 

V. The errors incident to the employment of the va- 



TO INDUCTION. 275 

nous Inductive Methods have already been pointed out in 
our detailed description of each of these Methods, but it 
may be useful in this place to take note of certain forms 
of fallacy which appear to be common to them all. 

The Inductive Methods may all be regarded as de- 
vices for the elimination of extraneous circumstances and 
for the establishment of a causal connection between some 
two phenomena, a and b, the connection which it is sought 
to establish being generally that of cause and effect. 
Now, in our investigation, we may either have mistaken 
the precise relation between a and b, or we may have 
overlooked some other material circumstance or group 
of circumstances, c. In the former case, the most 
common sources of error are either the inversion of 
cause and effect or the neglect of their reciprocal action, 
the 'mutuality of cause and effect,' as it is called by 
Sir G. C Lewis. In the latter case (supposing a to 
be the presumed cause, and b the presumed effect), it 
seems open to us to have committed any of the following 
errors: (i) to have mistaken a for the cause, when the 
real cause is r; (2) to have mistaken a for the sole cause, 
when a and c are the joint causes, either (a) as both 
contributing to the total effect, or (iS) as being both essen- 
tial to the production of any effect whatever''; (3) to 

® The distinction may be illustrated by a familiar example. If a 
cistern is filled by two pipes, the water passing through each contributts 
to the total amount of water in the cistern. But, if the cistern is filled 
by one pipe having two taps, one above the other, both taps must be 
turned m order that the cistern may receive any water whatever. 

T 2 



276 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

have mistaken a for the cause of by when they are really 
both of them effects of c ; (4) to have mistaken a for 
the proximate cause of 3, when it is really only the re- 
mote cause, c, which has escaped our attention, being 
the proximate cause. 

To begin with the latter class of errors. 

(i) The following extract from Mr. Lewes* Physiology 
of Common Life^ may serve as an illustration of the first 
subdivision : — 

* One very general, indeed almost universal, misconception 
on this subject (asphyxia or suffocation) is, that carbonic acid 
is poisonous in the blood ; but the truth seems to be that the 
carbonic acid is noxious only when it prevents the access 
of oxygen. There is always carbonic acid in the blood, both 
venous and arterial. Its accumulation in the blood is only 
fatal when there is such an accumulation in the atmosphere 
as will prevent its exhalation ; its mere presence in the blood 
seems to be quite harmless, even in large quantities, provided 
always that it be not retained there to the exclusion of 
oxygen. Carbonic acid, when absorbed into the blood, which 
is alkaline, cannot there exert its irritant action as an acid, 
because it will either be transformed into a carbonate or be 
dissolved. Bernard has injected large quantities into the 
veins and arteries, and under the skin of rabbits, and found 
no noxious effect ensue. The more carbonic acid there is 
in the blood, the more will be exhaled, provided always that 
the air be not already so charged with it as to prevent this 
exhalation.' 

Here there are really two antecedents, the presence 
of carbonic acid and the absence of oxygen, and the 
noxious effects, which are erroneously ascribed to the 

2* Vol. i. p. 383. 



TO INDUCTION, 277 

former cause, ought properly to be referred to the 
latter. 

The above extract exemplifies this error as vitiating 
an application of the Method of Agreement. In the 
following extracts from Dr. Paris' Pharmacologia, it will 
be seen also to vitiate applications of the Method of 
Difference : — 

* Soranus, who was contemporary with Galen, and wrote 
the life of Hippocrates, tells us that honey proved an easy 
remedy for the aphthae of children ; but instead of at once 
referring the fact to the medical qualities of the honey, he 
very gravely explains it, from its having been taken from 
bees that hived near the tomb of Hippocrates ^ ! * 

*In my life of Sir Humphry Davy, I have published an 
anecdote which was communicated to me by the late Mr. 
Coleridge, and which bears so strikingly upon the present 
subject that I must be excused for repeating it. As soon 
as the powers of nitrous oxide were discovered. Dr. Beddoes 
at once concluded that it must necessarily be a specific for 
paralysis: a patient was selected for the trial, and the 
management of it was entrusted to Davy. Previous to the 
administration of the gas, he inserted a small pocket thermo- 
meter under the tongue of the patient, as he was accustomed 
to do upon such occasions, to ascertain the degree of animal 
temperature, with a view to future comparison. The paralytic 
man, wholly ignorant of the nature of the process to which 
he was to submit, but deeply impressed, from the represent- 
ations of Dr. Beddoes, with the certainty of its success, no 
sooner felt the thermometer under his tongue, than he 
concluded the talisman was in full operation, and in a burst 
of enthusiasm declared that he already experienced the effect 

^ Pkarmacologiat p. so. 



278 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

of its benign influence throughout his whole body: the 
opportunity was too tempting to be lost ; Davy cast an 
intelligent glance at Mr. Coleridge, and desired his patient 
to renew his visit on the following day, when the same 
ceremony was performed, and repeated every succeeding day 
for a fortnight, the patient gradually improving during that 
period, when he was dismissed as ciu-ed, no other application 
having been used ^.' 

'Amongst the numerous instances which have been cited 
to show the power of faith over disease, or of the mind over 
the bodily organs, the cures performed by royal touch have been 
considered the most extraordinary : but it would appear, upon 
the authority of Wiseman, that the cures which were thus 
effected were in reality produced by a very different cause ; 
for he states that part of the duty of the royal physicians and 
Serjeant surgeons was to select such patients afflicted with 
scrofula as evinced a tendency towards recovery, and that 
they took especial care to choose those who approached the 
age of puberty. In short, those only were produced whom 
Nature had shown a disposition to cure ; and as the touch of 
the king, like the sympathetic power of Digby, secured the 
patient from the mischievous importimities of art, so were the 
efforts of Nature left free and uncontrolled, and the cure of 
the disease was not retarded or opposed by the administration 
of adverse remedies. The wonderful cures of Valentine 
Greatricks, performed in 1666, which were witnessed by 
contemporary prelates, members of parliament, and fellows 
of the Royal Society, amongst whom was the celebrated 
Mr. Boyle, would probably, upon investigation, admit of 
a similar explanation. It deserves, however, to be noticed, 
that in all records of extraordinary cures performed by 
mysterious agents, there has always been a desire to conceal 

•'* Pbarmacologiat p. 28. 



TO INDUCTION. 279 

the remedies, and other curative means which might have 
been simultaneously administered. Thus Oribasius com- 
mends, in high terms, a necklace of peony-root for the cure 
of epilepsy ; but we learn that he always took care to accom- 
pany its use with copious evacuations, although he assigns 
to them not the least share of credit in the cure. In later 
times, we have an excellent specimen of this species of 
deception, presented to us in a work on scrofula by Mr. 
Morley, written, as we were informed, for the sole purpose 
of restoring the much-injured character and use of the 
vervain ; in which the author directs the root of that plant 
to be tied with a yard of<ivbite satin riband around the neck ; 
— but mark — during the period of its application, he calls 
to his aid the most active medicines in the materia medica. 
" It is unquestionable," says Voltaire, speaking of sorceries, 
"that certain words and ceremonies will effectually destroy 
a flock of sheep, if administered with a sufficient portion 
of arsenic^." ' 

* Our inability upon all occasions to appreciate the efforts of 
nature in the cure of disease, must necessarily render our 
notions, with respect to the powers of art, liable to numerous 
errors and deceptions. Hence protracted or (wire-drawn 
cures ought to be very cautiously received as evidences of the 
success of medical treatment. Many diseases require only 
time to enable nature to remove them. All the long train 
connected with hysteria are cured by time; the solution of 
which, as Mr. Travers has observed, is to be found in the 
fact, that the hysteric period wanes, and the restlessness of 
the temperament undergoes a slow but salutary change. 
Nothing, certainly, is more natural, although it may be very 
erroneous, than to attribute the cure of a disease to the last 
medicine that had been administered ; the advocates even of 
amulets and charms have been thus enabled to appeal to 

^ Pbarmacdogiaf p. 30. 



a8o FALLACIES INCIDENT 

the testimony of what they call experience, in justification 
of their superstition^.' 

Of a similar character was the old superstition, noticed 
by Sir Thomas Browne ^ and many other authors, that 
the hardest stone could be broken by goat's blood : — 

' And, first, we hear it in every mouth, and in many good 
authors read it, that a diamond, which is the hardest of 
stones, not yielding unto steel, emery, or any thing but its 
own powder, is yet made soft, or broke by the blood of a 
goat. . . . But this, I perceive, is easier affirmed than 
proved. For lapidaries, and such as profess the art of cutting 
this stone, do generally deny it; and they that seem to 
countenance it have in their deliveries so qualified it, that 
little from thence of moment can be inferred for it. For 
first, the holy fathers, without a further enquiry, did take it 
for granted, and rested upon the authority of the first deliver- 
ers. . . . But the words of Pliny, from whom most likely 
the rest at first derived it, if strictly considered, do rather 
overthrow, than any way advantage this effect. His words 
are these: Hircino rumpitur sanguine, nee aliter quam recenti, 
calidoque macerata, et sic quoque multis ictibus, tunc etiatn prtBter^ 
quam eximias incudes malleosque ferreos frangens. That is, it is 
broken with goat's blood, but not except it be fresh and warm, 
and that not without many blows, and then also it will break 
the best anvils and hammers of iron.* 

The example of Sir Kenelm Digby's sympathetic pow- 
der (already quoted p. 252) also illustrates this class of 
fallacies *°. 

^ PbarmacologiOt p. 88. 

* Enquiry into Vulgar and Common Errors^ Bk. II, ch. v. Collected 
Works, vol. ii. pp. 334, 335. 

*® These instances, together with many others in this chapter, il- 
lustrate the ancient fallacies *Non causa pro causa* and * Post hoc, ergo 



TO INDUCTION. 28 1 

(2) When an effect is the joint result of two or more 
causes, the causes may either simply contribute towards 
the production of the total result, though one only would 
produce some portion of it, or they may all be essential 
to the production of any result whatever. It would be 
convenient if, in the former case, we could speak of the 
causes 2l% joint causes^ in the latter 2k% joint conditions ^ but 
to do so would perhaps be too great an innovation on 
established language. 

(a) An instance of supposing that a phenomenon is en- 
tirely due to one cause, when it seems in reality to be only 
partially due to it, is furnished by the notion, apparently 
erroneous, that the heart is the sole cause of the cir- 
culation of the blood. 

* What is it,* says Mr. Lewes *^, * which causes the blood to 
circulate ? " The heart," answers an unhesitating reader. 
That the heart pumps blood incessantly into the arteries, and 
that this pumping must drive the stream onwards with great 

propter hoc* It will probably have already occurred to the student that 
some of the examples just cited might have been equally well adduced as 
examples of the fallacy of noii-observation. It, in fact, frequently happens 
that the same error may be assigned indifferently to two or more sources 
of deception. * From the elliptical form,' says Archbishop Whately 
{Elements of Logic ^ Bk, iii. §1), * in which all reasoning is usually ex- 
pressed, and the peculiarly involved and oblique form in which fallacy is 
for the most part conveyed, it must of course be often a matter of doubt, 
or rather of arbitrary choice, not only to which genus each hind of fallacy 
should be referred, but even to which kind to refer any one individual 
fallacy.* Thus, so intimately are our intellectual operations blended, that 
it is often extremely difficult to decide whether a mistake be mainly due 
to defective observation or erroneous reasoning. 
** Physiology 0/ Common Life, vol. i. p. 323. 



282 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

force, there is no doubt; but although the most powerful 
agent in the circulation, the heart is not the sole agent - and 
the more we study this difficult question, the more our doubts 
gather round the explanation. 

* Let a few of the difficulties be stated. There have been 
cases of men and animals bom without a heart ; these ** acar- 
diac monsters" did not live, indeed could not live ; but they 
had grown and developed in the womb, and consequently 
their blood must have circulated. In most of these cases 
there has been a twin embryo, which was perfect ; and the 
circulation in both was formerly attributed to the heart of 
the one ; but it has been fully established that this is not the 
case. Further, Dr. Carpenter reminds us that " it has occa- 
sionally been noticed that a degeneration in the structure of 
the heart has taken place, during life, to such an extent that 
scarcely any muscular tissue could at last be detected in 
it, but without any such interruption to the circulation as 
must have been anticipated if this organ furnishes the sole 
impelling force." On the other hand, an influence acting on 
the capillaries will give a complete check to the action of 
the heart although that organ is itself perfectly healthy and 
vigorous.* 

Mr. Lewes then proceeds to discuss the subject at 
greater length, but the above quotation will be sufficient 
for our purpose. 

A familiar instance of this error occurs in the vulgar 
notion that the mean annual temperature of a place is 
exclusively determined by its latitude. The reader need 
hardly be told that in this case there are many other 
causes at work, namely, elevation, distance from the sea, 
proximity of mountain chains, and the like. 

When a number of causes contribute towards the total 



TO INDUCTION. %%i 

effect, it is plain that, as in the last instance, they may 
operate in the way of modifying, counteracting, or even 
frustrating*^ each other's influence. This is a considera- 
tion which it is often of the utmost importance to bear 
in mind, as will be obvious from the following examples, 
extracted, the former from Dr. Paris' Pharmacologia *^, the 
latter from Sir G. C. Lewis' Methods of Observation and 
Reasoning in Politics **. 

* In ordering saline draughts as vehicles for active medicines, 
it is very important that they should be rendered perfectly 
neutral; the effect of a predominating acid or alkali may 
produce decompositions fatal to the efficacy of the remedy, 
as the practitioner will fully understand by a reference to the 
Acetate of Ammonia^ and other preparations in the Table of 
Incompatibles. In prescribing them to be taken in a state of 
effervescence, we must consider whether the disengaged car- 
bonic acid may not invalidate the powers of the remedies 
simultaneously given with them. I should certainly recom- 
mend such a form to be avoided, in all cases where a salt 
of lead had been administered, for the carbonic acid retained 
in the stomach might probably convert it into a carbonate, 

* But it is to be borne in mind that, in estimating negative 
instances, due allowance must be made for the occasional 

frustration of causes For example : it might be 

argued, from the occurrence of several cases in which the 
absence of high import duties and of commercial restrictions 
was accompanied with abundance and cheapness of com- 
modities, that the former was the cause of the latter. Certain 

*^ We sometimes speak of causes * wholly or partially counteracting 
each other/ It would be an advantage, if we could appropriate the 
word frustration to express complete counteraction. 

^ p. 498. ** Vol. i. p. 386. 



284 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

instances might then occur, in which the former existed with- 
out the latter; but each of these exceptional cases might 
be accounted for, by showing that there was a special circum- 
stance, such as a deficient supply, or interruption of inter- 
course by war or blockade, which partially obstructed, and for 
a time suspended, the operation of the former cause. Again : 
it might be shown, by the evidence of facts, that the operation 
of a new law had been generally beneficial, with the exception 
of certain districts, where its enforcement had been prevented 
or retarded by certain peculiar and accidental circumstances. 
Exceptions of this kind,' which admit of an adequate special 
explanation, serve rather to confirm the general inference 
than to weaken it ; inasmuch as they raise the presumption 
that, but for the partial obstruction to the cause, it would 
have operated in these as in the other instances where no 
obstructions existed*^.* 

* It is probably from observing this case of the problem 
of causation, that the popular error has arisen of supposing 
that a rule is sometimes proved by its exceptions. Every 
exception to a general proposition must, in so far as it is 
an exception, detract from the application of the proposition, 
and consequently disprove [or rather go towards disproving] 
it. Thus, if it were asserted that all cloven-footed animals 
ruminate, this assertion certainly would receive no confirm- 
ation from the fact, that certain cloven-footed animals — such 
as the hog — do not ruminate. If, however, the exception, 
as in the case which we have been examining, admitted 
of a peculiar explanation, and it could be shown that the 
n'uus or tendency of the cause was the same in the excep- 
tional as in the other instances, but that in the former it 
was counteracted and overcome, while in the latter it was 
not — then the exception may be said not to invalidate, but 
rather to confirm the rule.* 

^ Sir G. C. Lewis' Methods of Observation and Reasoning in Politics, 
vjl. i. p. 386. 



TO INDUCTION. 285 

The above passage is noteworthy, as furnishing a good 
comment on the maxim, Exceptio probat regulam, a 
maxim which is, of course, only applicable where the 
exceptions are apparent, and where they admit of ex- 
planation in conformity with the rule. 

(/3) That every event depends upon the concurrence of 
a number of causes, positive and negative, or, as they 
are often called, conditions, has already been pointed 
out (Chap. I. pp. 10-12). Thus, the burning of a 
fire depends not only on the application of a lighted 
match and the supply of fuel, but also on the presence 
of atmospheric air, or rather of the oxygen which it 
contains, though, from the universal presence of air, we 
are less apt to think of the latter cause than of the former 
ones. The importance, however, of not overlooking this 
consideration is shewn by the extent to which we can 
augment the temperature by constantly bringing fresh 
currents of air into contact with any heated mass, as well 
as by the familiar phenomenon of the increased bright- 
ness with which a fire bums on a frosty day, when the 
atmosphere is more than ordinarily dry, or free from 
aqueous vapour. 

The importance of bearing in mind that an event 
depends upon a concurrence of causes may be further 
illustrated by the boiling-point of water. The point at 
which water boils depends upon two causes or con- 
ditions, the temperature of the water and the pressure 
of the atmosphere. Now, as the latter varies at diflferent 
heights and in different states of weather, water does not 



286 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

always boil at the same temperature^ the boiling-point 
being, as a rule, diminished by i** for every 590 feet that 
we ascend, so that, whereas at the sea level water boils 
at about 212° Fahrenheit, on the top of Mont Blanc it 
boils at about 185°. It is obvious that any one, not bear- 
ing in mind this fact, might be exposed to the greatest 
practical inconveniences. 

The following quotations from Dr. Paris' JPharmaco- 
hgia will furnish a suflfieient illustration of the importance 
of this consideration and of the errors which may result 
from neglecting it. 

* In some cases of irritability of stomach, the addition of a 
small quantity of opium will impart efficacy to a remedy 
otherwise inert ; an emetic will often thus be rendered more 
active, as I have frequently witnessed in my practice. In 
some states of mania, and affections of the brain, emetics will 
wholly fail, unless the stomach be previously influenced and 
prepared by a narcotic. I have often also found that the 
system has been rendered more susceptible of the influence 
of mercury by its combination with antimony and opium. 
So, again, when the system is in that condition which is 
indicated by a hot and dry skin, squill will fail in exciting 
expectoration; but administer it in conjunction with am- 
monia, and in some cases with Ant'tmomal Wine and a saline 
draughty and its operation will be promoted. As a diuretic, 
Squill is by no means active, when singly administered, but 
Calomel^ or some mercurial, when in combination with it, 
appears to direct its influence to the kidneys, and in some 
unknown manner to render these organs more susceptible of 
its influence*'*.* 

*• PbarmacolopOt p. 388. 



TO INDUCTION. 287 

*It has been determined by the most ample experience, 
that substances will produce effects upon the living system, 
when presented in a state of simple mechanical mixture, 
very different from those which the same medicinal ingre- 
dients will occasion when they are combined by the agency 
of chemical affinity. To illustrate this by a simple case, — a 
body suspended in a mixtiu^e in the form of a powder, will 
act very differently if held in solution by a fluid. The rela- 
tive effects of alcohol in the form of what is termed " spirit" 
and in that of wine, may be explained upon the same prin- 
ciple ; in the former case, it is in a state of mixture, in the 
latter, in that of combination. It has been demonstrated 
beyond all doubt, that a bottle of port, madeira, or sherry, 
actually contains as much alcohol as exists in a pint of 
brandy; and yet how different the effect! — a fact which 
affords a very striking illustration of the extraordinary 
powers of chemical con^ination in modifying the activity 
of substances upon the living system '"^.^ 

* It has been very generally supposed that substances, 
whose application does not produce any sensible action upon 
the healthy system, cannot possess medicinal energy ; and, on 
the contrary, that those which occasion an obvious effect 
must necessarily prove active in the cure or palliation of 
disease. To this general proposition, imder certain limita- 
tions and restrictions, we may perhaps venture to yield our 
assent ; but it cannot be too early, nor too forcibly impressed 
upon the mind of the young practitioner, that medicinej are, 
for the most part, but relative agents , producing their ejffects in 
reference only to the state of the living frame. We must, there- 
fore, concur with Sir Gilbert Blane in stating that the virtues 
of medicines cannot be fairly essayed, nor beneficially ascer- 
tained, by trying their effects on sound subjects, because that 
particular morbid condition does not exist which they may be 

** Pbarmaeologia, pp. 426, 427. 



288 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

exclusively calculated to remove ; thus, in a robust state of 
the body, the effects of steel, in commendation of which, in 
certain diseases, professional opinion is unanimous, may be 
wholly imperceptible. Bitter tonics, also, may either prove 
entirely inert, or they may give strength, relax the bowels, or 
induce constipation, according to the particular condition of 
the patient to whom they are administered ; so again in a 
healthy state of the stomach, a few grains of soda or magnesia 
will not occasion the least sensible effect, but where that 
organ is infested with a morbid acid, immediate relief will 
follow the ingestion of the one, and purgation that of the 
other. By not reasoning upon such facts, physicians have, in 
my opinion, very unphilosophically advanced to conclusions 
respecting the inefficacy of certain agents. They have ad- 
ministered particular preparations in large doses, and not 
having observed any visible effects, have at once denounced 
them as inert. I might allude, for instance, to the tris-tutraU 
of bismuth, a substance which, however powerless in health, I 
am well satisfied, from ample experience, is highly effica- 
cious in controlling certain morbid states of the stomach. 
Dr. Robertson has well observed, that disease calls forth 
the powers, and modifies the influence of medicines. That 
which agitates the calm of health may soothe the irritation 
of illness, and that which without opposition is inert, may 
act powerfully where it meets with an opponent. Experi- 
ments should be made on the sick, in order to determine how 
the sick will be affected, and nothing should be pronounced 
feeble, merely because it has done nothing where there was 
nothing to be done*\* 

To adduce one more illustration: insanity, though 
sometimes due to a number of causes, each one of 
which simply contributes to and augments the affection, 

^ Pbarmacologiaf pp. 133, 134. 



TO INDUCTION. ^89 

which would still exist, though in a weaker degree, 
even if some of them were absent, appears at other 
times to be the joint result of a number of causes, the 
presence of every one of which seems to be essential to 
the production of any effect so definite as to deserve the 
name of mental derangement. The train, in these cases, 
appears to be laid by a number of precedent circum- 
stances, and the addition of some one other circumstance 
seems to be the spark which produces the conflagration. 

*When we are told,* says Dr. Maudsley**, *that a man 
has become deranged from anxiety or grief, we have 
learned very little if we rest content with that. How does it 
happen that another man, subjected to an exactly similar 
cause of grief, does not go mad ? It is certain that the entire 
causes cannot be the same where the effects are so different ; 
and what we want to have laid bare is the conspiracy of 
conditions, internal and external, by which a mental shock, 
inoperative in one case, has had such serious consequences 
in another. A complete biographical account of the indi- 
vidual, not neglecting the consideration of his hereditary 
antecedents, would alone suffice to set forth distinctly the 
causation of his insanity. If all the circumstances, internal 
and external, were duly scanned and weighed, it would be 
found that there is no accident in madness; the disease, 
whatever form it might take, by whatsoever complex con- 
currence of conditions, or by how many successive links of 
causation, it might be generated, would be traceable as the 
inevitable consequence of certain antecedents, as plainly as 
the explosion of gunpowder may be traced to its causes, 
whether the train of events of which it is the issue be long 

*' Physiology and Pathology of Mind, Part II. ch. i. p. 325. 

U 



290 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

or short. The germs of insanity are sometimes latent in 
the foundations of the character, and the final outbreak is 
perhaps the explosion of a long train of antecedent prepa- 
rations. 

(3) The phenomena of insanity also furnish a good illus- 
tration of the next source of error, the mistaking of joint 
effects for cause and effect. In this, as in many other 
diseases, symptoms are often mistaken for causes. Thus, 
it is not uncommon to hear violent religious excitement 
or inordinate grief adduced as causes of insanity, whereas 
these are probably, in the vast majority of cases, due to 
precisely the same combination of physical and mental 
causes which, when they operate with greater intensity, 
ultimately issue in definite and unmistakable insanity. 

We have an instructive instance of the same error 
in some of the speculations respecting the origin of 
fevers. In Abdominal Typhus (the so-called TyphoVd 
or Enteric Fever of the English Physicians) the febrile 
symptoms (Pyrexia, Erethism, &c.) have been as- 
cribed to certain lesions of the glandular structures 
of the intestines; but a wider observation has shown 
that the other symptoms often precede by some time 
the formation of the lesions, and that the fever may 
even run a fatal course, though it may be impossible, 
in a post-mortem examination, to detect the specific 
lesions in question. Practically, the correction of this 
and similar errors is of great importance, as much mis- 
chief may be done, and much time may be lost, by a 
mode of treatment which, through mistaking sjmtiptoms 



TO INDUCTION. 291 

for causes, or co-eflfects for cause and effect, addresses 
itself only to the consequences of the malady, and leaves 
the real source of evil unattacked. 

The following anecdote, told by Dr. Paris, affords an 
amusing illustration of the extent to which the ignorant, 
in reasoning on cause and effect, may be deceived by an 
invariable, or even frequent, concurrence of events. 

* It should,' says he'^, ^be kept in mind, that two events 
may arise from a common cause, and be co- existent, 
and yet have not the most remote analogy to, or de- 
pendence upon, each other. It was a general belief at 
St. Kilda, that the arrival of a ship gave all the inhabitants 
colds. Dr. John Campbell took a great deal of pains to 
ascertain the fact, and to explain it as the effect of effluvia 
arising from human bodies ; the simple truth, however, was, 
that the situation of St. Kilda renders a north-east wind 
indispensably necessary before a stranger can land, — the 
wind, not the stranger, occasioned the epidemic' 

In speculations on the history of language, languages, 
which recent investigation has shown to be related col- 
laterally, were by older philologers erroneously regarded 
as standing to each other in the relation of parent and 
child. I extract from Professor Max Mtiller's Lectures 
on the Science of Language^^ the foUovring illustration, 
which will aheady be familiar to many of my readers : — 

* A glance at the modem history of language will make 
this clearer. There never could be any doubt that the so- 

"• Pbarmacologia, p. 89 " First Series Lecture V, 

U 2 



293 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

called Romance languages, Italian, Wallachian, Provenga 
French, Spanish, and Portuguese, were closely related to ei 
other. Everybody could see that they were all derived fr 
Latin. But one of the most distinguished French schoi; 
Raynouard, who has done more for the history of the F 
mance languages and literature than any one else, maintah 
that ProveiifaJ only was the daughter of Latin ; when 
French, Italian, Spanish, and Portuguese were the daughl 
of Provencal. He maintained that Latin passed, from 1 
seventh to the ninth century, through an intermediate sta 
which he called Langue Romane, and which he eadeavoui 
to prove was the same as the Proven9al of Southern FraO' 
the language of the Troubadours. According to him, it v 
only after Latin had passed through this uniform metamt 
phosis, represented by the Langue Romane or Provenf 
that it became broken up into the various Romance dialei 
of Italy, France, Spain, and Portugal. This theory, whi 
was vigorously attacked by August Wilhelm von Schleg 
and afterwards minutely criticised by Sir Comewall Lew 
can only be refuted by a comparison of the Proven) 
grammar with that of the other Romance dialects. And hei 
if you take the auxiliary verb Ib be, and compare its fon 
in Proven9al and French, you will see at once that, 1 
several points, French has preserved the original Latin fbn 
in a more primitive state than Proven5al, and that, therefoi 
it is impossible to classify French as the daughter of Pr 
venial, and as the granddaughter of Latin. We have 
Proven 5 al ; — 

" The met relationship of French to Provenj»l may be repretenl 
thus ; the Pensant Latin becime in the South of France the L»n| 
d'Oe (or Provenfal), ind in the North the Langue d'Oi], of which 1 
French (or the dialed of the Isle de France) was the principal diale 
and his in its modem tonn became the language of the natjon. * 
Brachet'i HisloriccU Qrammar (Mr. Khcbui's Tiaoilation), p. 13, 



TO INDUCTION. ^93 

senij corresponding to the French nous sommes^ 
et% „ *vous etes, 

son ,y Us sontf 

and it would be a grammatical miracle if crippled forms, such 
as sem, etz, and son, had been changed back again into the 
more healthy, more primitive, more Latin, sommes, etes, sont ; 
sumus, estis, sunt. 

Let us apply the same test to Sanskrit, Greek, and Latin ; 
and we shall see how their mutual genealogical position is 
equally determined by a comparison of their grammatical 
forms. It is as impossible to derive Latin from Greek, or 
Greek from Sanskrit, as it is to treat French as a modification 
of Provengal. Keeping to the auxiliary verb to be, we find 
that / am is in 

Sanskrit Greek Lithuanian 

asmi esmi esmi. 

The root is as, the termination mi. 

Now, the termination of the second person is si, which, 
together with as, or es, would make, 

as'si eS'Si es'si. 

But here Sanskrit, as far back as its history can be traced, 
has reduced assi to asi ; and it would be impossible to suppose 
that the perfect, or, as they are sometimes called, organic, 
forms in Greek and Lithuanian, es-si, could first have passed 
through the mutilated state of the Sanskrit asi. 

The third person is the same in Sanskrit, Greek, and 
Lithuanian, as-ti or es-ti; and, with the loss of the final /, we 
recognise the Latin est, Gothic ist, and Russian est*. 

The same auxiliary, verb can be made to furnish sufficient 
proof that Latin never could have passed through the Greek, 
or what used to be called the Pelasgic stage, but that both 
are independent modifications of the same original language. 
In the singular, Latin is less primitive than Greek ; for sum 
stands for es-um, es for es-is, est for es-ti. In the first person 



294 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

plural, too, sumus stands for es-umus, the Greek ej^meSf the 
Sanskrit *smas. The second person «-^w, is equal to Greek 
es-te^ and more primitive than Sanskrit stba. But in the third 
person phiral Latin is more primitive than Greek. The 
regular form would be as-anti; this, in Sanskrit^ is changed 
into janti. In Greek, the initial s is dropped, and the iEolic 
enti is finally reduced to eisi. The Latin, on the contrary, 
has kept the radical j, and it would be perfectly impossible 
to derive the Latin sunt from the Greek eLsL' 

(4) A not uncommon som"ce of error is the confusion 
of the proximate with the primary or remote cause of 
a phenomenon. To be on our guard against this error 
is often of the utmost practical importance ; for the re- 
moval of the proximate cause may only temporarily 
remove the eflfect, and the primary cause may, after a 
time, reproduce it ; or, again, the removal of the primary 
cause may still leave the proximate cause in full action. 
This is well exemplified in Mr. Lewes' account of Thirst. 

'The sensation of Thirst is not merely a sensation de- 
pendent on a deficiency of liquid in the system, but a local sen- 
sation dependent on a local disturbance : the more water these 
men (the prisoners confined in the Black Hole at Calcutta) 
drank, the more dreadful seemed their thirst ; and the mere 
sight of water rendered the sensation, which before was 
endurable, quite intolerable. The increase of the sensation 
following a supply 6i water, would be wholly inexplicable to 
those who maintain that the proximate cause of Thirst is 
deficiency of liquid; but is not wholly inexplicable, if we 
regard the deficiency as the primary, not the proximate 
cause; for this primary cause having set up a feverish con- 
dition in the mouth and throat, that condition would continue 
after the original cause had ceased to exist. The stimulus 



TO INDUCTION. 295 

of cold water is only a momentary relief in this case, and 
exaggerates the sensation by stimulating a greater flow o( 
blood to the parts. If, instead of cold water, a little luke- 
warm tea, or milk-and-water, had been dnmk, permanent 
relief would have been attained ; or if, instead of cold water, 
a lump of ice had been taken into the mouth, and allowed 
to melt there, the effect would have been very different — 
a transitory application of cold increasing the flow of blood, 
a continuous application driving it away. 

*We must not, however, forget that although, where a 
deficiency of liquid has occasioned a feverish condition of the 
mouth and throat, no supply of cold liquid will at once re- 
move that condition, the relief of the Systemic sensation 
not immediately producing relief of the local sensation, never- 
theless, so long as the system is in need of liquid, the feeling 
of thirst must continue. Claude Bernard observed that a 
dog which had an opening in its stomach drank unceasingly, 
because the water ran out as fast as it was swallowed; in 
vain the water moistened mouth and throat on its way to 
the stomach. Thirst was not appeased because the water 
was not absorbed. The dog drank till fatigue forced it to 
pause, and a few minutes afterwards recommenced the same 
hopeless toil ; but no sooner was the opening closed, and the 
water retained in the stomach, from whence it was absorbed 
into the system, than thirst quickly vanished*'.' 

In studying the history of a language, it is often 
most important to bear in mind that words ultimately 
derived from one language are proximately derived 
through the medium of another. Thus, 'there are in- 
deed,' says M. Brachet'^, * some few Greek words in early 

® Lewes' Physiology of Common Life, vol. i. pp. 45-47. 
^ Historical Grammar, Mr. Kitchio's Translation, p. 37. 



2g6 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

French, such as ckhe, somme, parole; but these do not 
come straight from the Greek ko^cl, aayfia, n-apafioXij, but 
through the Latin which first adopted them and handed 
them on/ And again : — 

* When Jerome translated the Old Testament into Latin 
he incorporated into his version certain Hebrew "words which 
had no Latin equivalents, as seraphim, Gehenna, pascha, &c. ; 
from Latin they passed at a later time into French (seraphiny 
gene, pdque'). But they entered French from the Latin, not 
from the Hebrew. The same is the case with the Arabic; 
its relations with French have been purely accidental. To 
say nothing of those words which express oriental things 
such as Alcoran, bey, cadi, cara'vane, dervicbe, firmany jamssaire, 
&c., which were brought into the west by travellers, the 
French language received, in the middle ages, many Arabic 
words from another source : the Crusades, the scientific 
greatness of the Arabians, the study of oriental philosophies, 
much followed in France between the twelfth and fourteenth 
centuries, enriched the vocabulary of the language with many 
words belonging to the three sciences which the Arabians 
cultivated successfully: in astronomy it gave such words as 
azimuth, nadir, zenith; in alchemy, alcali, alcool, alambic, 
alchimie, elixir, sirop; in mathematics, algebre, n^ro, chiffre. 
But even so these words did not come directly from Arabic 
to French ; they passed through the hands of the scientific 
Latin of the middle ages. In fact, the oriental languages 
have had little or no popular or direct influence on French ".* 

The non-recognition of these intermediate channels 
through which the words of one language have been 
introduced into another, has often led to the most erro- 

" Historical Grammar, p. 22, a. 2. 



TO INDUCTION. %()'] 

neous theories as to the connection of languages or the 
relations subsisting between the people speaking them. 
Thus, it was once a favourite theory that all languages 
are derived from Hebrew, and the occurrence in dif- 
ferent languages of the same words has often, without 
any other ground, been regarded as a proof of the con- 
nection of the most diverse races. 

We add an example from the science of Political 
Economy. It has often been supposed that high prices 
produce high wages. A sudden rise in the price of any 
particular class of commodities may lead, by a desire 
on the part of the producers to increase the supply, and 
by a consequent increase in the demand for labour in 
that particular department, to a temporary rise in wages. 
But a rise in prices produces no permanent rise in wages, 
unless it leads to an increased accmnulation of capital, 
that is, an augmentation of the fund available for the 
further production of wealth aiid, consequently, for the 
payment of wages '^^. Here the rise in prices is the 
remote or primary, and the increased accumulation of 
capital is the proximate, cause of the phenomenon ; but, 
as counteracting causes, such as reckless speculation or 
the adoption of a more luxurious style of living on the 
part of the capitalists, may prevent the rise in prices 
from being followed by an increased accumulation of 
. capital, it is often of great importance to distinguish the 
two. 

We have, thus far, discussed those errors which ori- 

^ See Mill's Politieal Economy, Bk. II. ch. zi. § a. 



298 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

ginate in overlooking the presence of some third circum-^ 
stance. But, even when all the circumstances except the 
cause and effect (or what we suppose to be such) have 
been eliminated, we may still commit an error, either 
from mistaking the cause for the effect, or from neglect- 
ing to take account of their mutual action and reaction, 
and being thus led erroneously to assign to one of the 
two exclusively the whole share in the production of the 
ultimate effect. 

(5) The importance of not overlooking this latter source 
of error is well illustrated by the following remarks of 
Sir G. C. Lewis ^^:— 

*An additional source of error in determining political 
causation is likewise to be found in the mutuality of cause 
and effect. It happens sometimes that when a relation of 
causation is established between two facts, it is hard to 
decide which, in the given case, is the cause and which the 
effect, because they act and re-act upon each other, each 
phenomenon being in turn cause and effect. Thus, habits 
of industry may produce wealth ; while the acquisition of 
wealth may promote industry: again, habits of study may 
sharpen the understanding, and the increased acuteness of 
the understanding may afterwards increase the appetite for 
study. So an excess of population may, by impoverishing the 
labouring classes, be the cause of their living in bad dwellings; 
and, again, bad dwellings, by deteriorating the moral habits 
of the poor, may stimulate population. The general intelli- 
gence and good sense of a people may promote its good 
government, and the goodness of the government may, in its 
turn, increase the intelligence of the people, and contribute 

^ On Methods of Observation and Reasoning in Politics, vol. i. p. 375. 



TO INDUCTION. , 299 

to the formation of sound opinions among them. Dnmken- 
ness is in general the consequence of a low degree of intelli- 
gence, as may be observed both among savages and in civilized 
countries. But, in return, a habit of drunkenness prevents 
the cultivation of the intellect, and strengthens the cause 
out of which it grows. As Plato remarks, education im- 
proves nature, and nature facilitates education. National 
character, again, is both effect and cause : it re-acts on the 
circumstances from which it arises. The national peculiarities 
of a people, its race, physical structure, climate, territory, 
&c., form originally a certain character, which tends to 
create certain institutions, political and domestic, in har- 
mony with that character. These institutions strengthen, 
perpetuate, and reproduce the character out of which they 
grew, and so on in succession, each new effect becoming, 
in its turn, a new cause. Thus a brave, energetic, restless 
nation, exposed to attack from neighbours, organises military 
institutions: these institutions promote and maintain a war- 
like spirit : this warlike spirit, again, assists the development 
of the military organisation, and it is further promoted by 
territorial conquests and success in war, which may be its 
result— each successive effect thus adding to the cause out 
of which it sprung.' 

The difference between the calculated and observed 
velocities of sound (already noticed*®) furnishes another 
illustration of the importance of attending to the mutual 
action of cause and effect. The wave of sound, in its 
passage through the air, developes heat by compression, 
and this heat, by augmenting the elasticity of the air, 
increases, in turn, the velocity with which the sound 
is transmitted. Thus the effect re-acts upon, and pro- 

" pp. 171, 173. 



I 



1 



300 FALLACIES INCIDEITT 

motes the operation of, the original cause. It was fp 
overlooking this fact that Newton's calctUation of 
velocity of sound fell short of the observed velocity 
about one-sixth of the actual rate. 

Malthus' speculations on the increase of populat 
illustrate another form of the same error. He foi 
that, in many cases, population increased faster than ft 
increased. He inferred that this increase of populat 
once begun would continue under all circumstano 
and that therefore a time was at hand, in many coi 
tries, when the bulk of the people would be redui 
almost to a state of starvation. He did not obse; 
that in this case, the effect re-acts upon the cause ; n 
however, in the way of promotii^ but of retarding 
operation. The tendency of an increase of populati 
is certainly to diminish the supply of food; but, in 
tempting to forecast the ultimate results of this tt 
dency, Malthus did not take sufficient account of t 
fact that the diminution in the supply of food h; 
in its turn, a tendency to arrest the increase of pop 
lation. 

Instances of the tendency of an effect to re-act up" 
its cause, in the way of diminishing its intensity, are ve 
frequent in human aff^rs. Thus, when a man discove 
that he is labouring under a disease, the addition 
prudence which he is induced to exercise will ofti 
not only arrest or retard the progress of the diseaf 
but lead to the prolongation of his life beyond the usu 
term. Again, when a deficiency of sanitary arrang 



TO INDUCTION, 30r 

merits has led to an increased mortality or the outbreak 
of a pestilence, the attention thus directed to the noxious 
influences at work will often result in their removal, or, 
at least, in some considerable alleviation of them. It 
is plain that, in speculating on the future, these are 
considerations which ought not to be left out of ac- 
count. 

(6) We may invert cause and effect, mistaking one 
for the other. This error is not infrequent in his- 
torical speculations, as, for instance, when some great 
event, such as the religious reformation of the sixteenth 
century, or the French Revolution, is assigned as the 
cause of a general change of opinion or of certain mental 
and social habits, whereas, in reality, the gradual, and 
often imobserved, operation of this change has been the 
cause, and not the effect, of the historical event. In 
a case of this kind, however, the event may, in turn, 
have intensified, and, perhaps, given the sanction of 
authority to, the causes which produced it. 

Again, a particular form of government, monarchical, 
aristocratical, democratical, or the like, is often assigned 
as the cause of certain peculiarities of social feeling or 
national character, whereas it would probably be far 
more correct to regard the form of government as due, 
in the first instance, to these peculiarities, though it, in 
turn, may have intensified the causes to which it was 
originally due. 

In meteorological speculations it has been questioned 
whether the "electrical phenomenon of lightning is the 



302 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

cause or eflfect of the sudden precipitations of rain and 
hail which it generally accompanies. Sir John Herschel 
(in opposition to the ordinary opinion**') maintains that 
it is the effect, and argues thus : — 

* Whatever may be the state of the ultimate molecules of 
vapour, it seems impossible but that when a great multitude 
of them lose their vaporous state by cold, and coalesce into 
a drop or snow spangle, however minute, that drop will have 
collected and retained on its surface (according to the laws 
of electric equilibrium) the whole electricity of its con- 
stituent molecules, which will therefore have some finite, 
though very feeble tension. Now, suppose any number (looo 
for instance) of such globules to coalesce, or that by successive 
deposition one should gradually grow to looo times its original 
volume. The diameter will be only lo, and the surface loo 
times increased. But the electric contents being the sum 
of those of the elementary globules, will be increased one 
thousandfold, and being spread entirely over the surface, will 
have a tenfold density (j,e, tension). 

♦ * * * 4c 

* It will easily be seen, that when thousands of these electri- 
ferous globules again further coalesce into rain drops, a great 
and sudden increase of tension at their surface must take 
place. Their electricity, then, is enabled to spring from drop 
to drop, and rushing in an instant of time from all parts of 
the cloud to the surface, a flash is produced. Accordingly, 
in thunder-storms, it is the commonest of all phenomena to 
find each great flash succeeded by a sudden rush of rain at 
such an interval of time as may be supposed to have been 
occupied in its descent. The sudden precipitation of large 
quantities of rain, and especially of hail, which is formed in 
a cold region where the insulating power of the air is great 

* Herschel's Meteorology ^ §§ 135, 137. 



TO INDUCTION, 303 

is almost sure to be accompanied with lightning, which the 
usual perversity of meteorologists, where electricity is in 
question, long persisted, and even yet persists, with few ex- 
ceptions, in regarding as the cause, and not the consequence, 
of the precipitation.' 

A question has also been raised whether the copious 
precipitation of rain which usually takes place in the 
centre of a cyclone is the cause or the eflfect of the 
cyclone. The more probable view is that the partial 
vacuum produced by the rain-fall, and the consequent 
inrush of the surrounding atmosphere, is the cause of 
the cyclone. 

Professor Rogers, in his recently published Manual of 
Political Economy^, calls in question the received opinion 
on the relation between the increase of population and 
the cultivation of inferior soils. Though I cannot accept 
his position, the passage will serve as an instance of 
the difficulty frequently experienced in determining which 
of two phenomena or events is cause and which is 
effect. 

'There is not a shadow of evidence in support of the 
statement that inferior lands have been occupied and cul- 
tivated as population increases. The increase of population 
has not preceded but followed this occupation and cultivation. 
It is not the pressure of population on the means of sub- 
sistence which has led men to cultivate inferior soils, but the 
fact that these soils being cultivated in another way, or taken 
into cultivation, an increased population became possible. 
How could an increased population have stimulated greater 



60 



p. 153. 



304 FALLACIES ZZfCmETT 



hbcnr ia. agricuitare, wfioi a ^imltu re i«»*st : bv^ ijj,^_k,| 
the mcaas oq whicii tbat iiicrEa»i popizLitKxi conli bate 
exited ^^r To make inareased popalatioa tfie cam^ of m- 
proved agricuitnre is to cxjmmit the absurd blazidcr of coh 
foundxng caise and effect.' 

Whfle agreeizig wish the ordmarv tbeorr that Ae 
pressure of popoknon leads, in the first instance, to 
the cultivation of inferior lands, I shoold admit that die 

ideriz^ 



possible a larger population, reacts iq>on and intensifies 
the original cause, an increased population leading to die 
culdvation of fresh lands, that rendering possible a still 
larger population, this in turn leading to the cnltivatioD 
of fresh lands, and so on, till the process is arrested 
by counteracting causes. If this view be correct, die 
ordinary theory is more jusdy open to the cham 
of neglecting to take into account the 'mutuality' of 
cause and effect, noticed a few pages back, than of 
inverting their relatidlL 

VI. The Argument from Analogy, as has already been 
stated, consists in drawing the conclusion that, because 
two phenomena resemble each other in certain observed 
points, they also resemble each other in certain other 
points beyond the range of our observation. The con- 
ditions to which such an inference, in order to be leei- 
timate, must conform, need not be here repeated. If 
the conditions be not fulfilled, we may commit the error 

*^ This question appears to ignore the fact that a population may hare 
an insufficient supply of food, though it may just be able to sustain life. 



TO INDUCTION. 305 

either of over-estimating the force of the analogy; of 
mistaking the direction in which it points, so as to regard 
an analogy which makes against a certain position as 
making for it, or the reverse; or, lastly, of supposing 
grounds of analogy to subsist where there really are 
none. The two former errors have been sufl&ciently ex- 
emplified in the chapter on Imperfect Inductions. 

When we exaggerate the value of analogical evidence, 
or mistake the conclusion to be drawn from it, we may 
be led to do so either by over-rating the number of 
ascertained points of resemblance as compared with 
ascertained points of diflference, or the reverse, or by 
miscalculating the extent of our knowledge of the pheno- 
mena. The examples referred to illustrate both sources 
of error. Thus, for instance, the points in which elec- 
tricity resembles a fluid are obvious, while the points of 
difference are far less obtrusive, and, moreover, the un- 
known properties of electricity are probably out of all 
proportion to those which we know. In this case, too, 
when we include the consideration of heat, light, and 
simUar agencies, the argument from analogy may be 
used against, rather than in favour of, the identification 
of electricity with a fluid. 

The student need, however, hardly be reminded that 
an analogy which in one state of knowledge appears 
to be a strong one may, as knowledge advances, become 
extremely faint, worthless, or even positively unfavourable 
to the position which it was originally adduced to support. 

The term False Analogy is, strictly speaking, applied 

X 



3o6 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

not to those cases in which we over-estimate the value 
of the analogy, or mistake the direction in which the 
argument points, but to those cases of analogical in- 
ference in which there exists no ground for any analogy 
whatever. Two phenomena. A, B, resemble each other 
in the possession of the properties a, b^ c. The pheno- 
menon A is observed also to present the property d^ and 
hence it is inferred as probable that the same property 
is to be found also in B. Now it has already been 
pointed out that if we have any reason to suppose i 
to be causally connected with any of the properties 
a, b, Cy the argument ceases to be analogical, and b^ 
comes inductive. But if, on the other hand, we have 
any reason to suppose that d is causally connected with 
none of the properties a, 3, r, there is no room for any 
inference whatever. The whole force of the Argument 
from Analogy consists in the chance of d being causally 
connected with a, b, ox c] if we have reason to believe 
that this is the case, the argument becomes more than 
analogical; if we have reason to believe that it is not 
the case, we are debarred from employing the argument 
altogether. Thus, in a certain sense, the Argument from 
Analogy is based on our ignorance; it is the result of 
a calculation of chances, which an accession of know- 
ledge may invalidate, by either augmenting, diminishing, 
or annihilating. Of False Analogy, in its strict sense, 
that is to say, the error of supposing that similarity or 
dissimilarity in certain points is an evidence of similarity 
or dissimilarity in other points, when more careful re- 



TO INDUCTION. 307 

flection or observation would lead to the belief that there 
is probably no connection whatever between the ob- 
served points from which the Analogy proceeds, and the 
unobserved points to which it argues, instances are 
extremely numerous in almost every branch of knowledge. 
As this, form of Fallacy is so common, we shall subjoin 
several examples of it. 

The following excellent illustration is quoted by Mr. 
Mill from Archbishop Whately's Rhetoric *^ : 

* It would be admitted that a great and permanent diminu- 
tion in the quantity of some useful commodity, such as corn, 
or coal, or iron, throughout the world, would be a serious 
and lasting loss ; and again, that if the fields and coal mines 
yielded regularly double quantities, with the same labour, 
we should be so much the richer ; hence it might be inferred, 
that if the quantity of gold and silver in the world were 
diminished one half, or were doubled, like results would 
follow ; the utility of these metals, for the purposes of coin, 
being very great. Now there are many points of resemblance 
and many of difference, between the precious metals on the 
one hand, and corn, coal, &c. on the other ; but the important 
circumstance to the supposed argument is, that the utility of 
gold and silver (as coin, which is far the chief) depends on 
their value, which is regulated by their scarcity ; or rather, to 
speak strictly, by the difficulty of obtaining them; whereas, 
if corn and coal were ten times as abundant (i.e. more easily 
obtained), a bushel of either would still be as useful as now. 
But if it were twice as easy to procure gold as it is, a sove- 
reign would be twice as large ; if only half as easy, it would 

«2 MiU's Logic, Bk. V. ch. v. § 6 ; Whately's Rhetoric, Part I. ch. ii. 
§ 7. The passage does not occur in the earlier editions of Whately's 
Rhetoric. 

X 2 



308 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

hi of the size of a half-sovereign, and this (besides the trifling 
circumstance of the cheapness or clearness of gold ornaments) 
would be all the difference. The analogy, therefore, fails in 
the point essential to the argument/ 

Respect for antiquity is often urged by an argument 
so sweeping as to assume the form of a False AnaIog}^ 
'Who are we/ it is said, *that we should presume to 
think that we know better than previous generations?' 
Now, on many matters of fact, there can be no question 
that the belief of previous generations, when properly 
examined and sifted, must be accepted as final, inasmuch 
as they were contemporary with, or at least nearer than 
ourselves to, the original sources of information. To 
infer from this just and limited deference the necessity of 
an undiscriminating submission to the opinions of our 
ancestors, would be an instance of the fallacy of Inductio 
per simplicem enumerationem. But this, at least in 
many cases, seems not to be the nature of the argu- 
ment, which appears rather to proceed on the following 
grounds : we reverence the opinions of the aged, because 
they have had more experience than we have had, and 
, therefore, surely, on the same principle, we ought to 
accept the opinions of our ancestors who lived in bygone 
generations. The point of resemblance is the fact of 
having been born at a period prior to ourselves, and 
hence it is inferred that the greater experience and the 
greater wisdom which are found to be concomitants of 
this fact in the case of many of our senior contemporaries 
may also be presumed in the case of those who have 



TO INDUCTION. 309 

long since been dead. It, of course, escapes the notice 
of those who have recourse to this argument, that the 
average age of the persons living at any one time is 
about the same as that of those living at any other, and 
that superior wisdom is the consequence not of priority 
of birth but of greater experience. Thus far, the fallacy 
may be regarded as one of False Analogy, strictly so 
called. But there is another consideration which turns 
the edge of the argument. Experience grows with time, 
each generation not only inheriting the accumulated 
experience of previous generations, but adding to the 
stock its own acquisitions. 'Recte enim,' says Bacon ^, 
* Veritas temporis filia dicitur, non auctoritatis.' * Anti- 
quitas saeculi juventus mundi^/ 

^ Novum Organum, Bk. I. Aph. Ixxxiv. The reference is, perhaps, 
to ^schylus, Prometheus Vinctus, I. 981 : &XX* ixdi^aKci v6li/0' 6 
yrfpAaKojy xp6vo$. Compare the following sentences in the same 
Aphorism : * De antiquitate autem opinio, quam homines de ipsa fovent, 
negligens omnino est, et vix verbo ipsi congnia. Mundi enim senium 
et grandsBvitas pro antiquitate vere habenda sunt ; quae temporibus 
nostris tribui debent, non juniori aetati mundi, qualis apud antiquos fuit. 
Ilia enim aetas, respectu nostri, antiqua et major ; respectu mundi ipsius, 
nova et minor fuit. Atque revera quemadmodum majorem rerum huma- 
narum notitiam, et maturius judicium, ab horoine sene expectamus, quam 
a juvene, propter experientiam, et rerum, quas vidit, et audivit, et 
cogitavit, varietatem et copiam ; eodem modo et a nostra setate (si vires 
suas nosset, et experiri et intendere vellet) majora multo quam a priscis 
temporibus expectari par est ; utpote aetate mundi grandiore, et infinitis 
cxperimentis et observationibus aucta et cimiulata/ Bentham in his 
Book of Fallacies, Part I. ch. ii., and Sydney Smith in his review of that 
work {Edinburgh Review, No. Ixxxiv, reprinted in his Collected Works), 
have some very apposite and amusing remarks on this subject. 
•* De Augmentis Scientiarum, Lib. I. Dr. Whewell in his Pbihsopby 



3IO FALLACIES INCIDENT 

Bishop Wilkins' Discovery of a New World contains 
the following curious extract, translated from the woA 
of Cardinal Nicold de Cusa De doctd Ignorantid •* : 

* We may conjecture the inhabitants of the sun are like to 
the nature of that planet, more clear and bright, more intel- 
lectual than those in the moon where they are nearer to the 
nature of that duller planet, and those of the earth being 
more gross and material than either, so that these intellectual 
natures in the sun are more form than matter, those in the 

ofDhcovery (chap. xiii. % 4) appears to think that thif celebrated Apho- 
riim may be traced to Giordano Bruno. * It is worthy of remark that 
a thought which is often quoted from Francis Bacon, occurs in Bruno's 
Cena di Centre ^ pubh'shed in 15S4; I mean, the notion that the bter 
times are more aged than the earlier. In the course of the dialogue, the 
Pedant, who is one of the interlocutors, says, *'In antiquity is wisdom*" 
to which the Philosophical Character replies, ** If you knew what too 
were talking about, you would see that your prmciple leads to the 
opposite result of that which you wish to infer ; — I mean, that we are 
older, and have lived longer, than our predecessors." He then proceeds 
to apply this, by tracing the course o{ astronomy through the earlier 
astronomers up to Copernicus.* See Wagner's edition of Giordano 

Bruno*t Works, vol. i. p. 133. In the original the passage runs thus: 

* Prudenzio. Sii come la si vuole, io non voglio discostarmi dal parer de 
gli antichi; per che dice il saggio: Ne I'antiquitli k la sapienza. 
Teofilo. E soggiunge : In molti anni la prudenza. Se roi intendeste 
bene quel che dite, vedreste, che dal vostro fondamento s' inferisce il 
contrario di quel che pensate : voglio dire, che noi siamo piii vecchi et 
abbiamo piU lunga etk, che i nostri predecessori.' Mr. Spedding, how- 
ever, in his edition of Bacon, questions whether Bacon intended the 
aphorism as a quotation, and thinks it probable that he did not derive 
it from any earlier writer. See Ellis and Spedding's edition of B<ie<M 
vol. i. p. 458, n. 4. 

•' Wilkins* Diicovery o/a New World in the Moon, p. laS ; Cusanus, 
De doct(% IgnorantiA, Lib. II. ch. xii. 



TO INDUCTION. 3II 

earth more matter than form, and those in the moon betwixt 
both. This we may guess from the fiery influence of the sun, 
the watery and aerous influence of the moon, so also the 
material heaviness of the earth. In some such manner like- 
wise is it with the regions of the other stars ; for we conjec- 
ture that none of them are without inhabitants, but that there 
are so many particular worlds and parts of this one universe, 
as there are stars, which are innumerable, unless it be to Him 
who created all things in number.' 

The analogy in this case is founded not, as in the 
previous instances, on points of resemblance but on 
points of dissimilarity. The sun, the moon, and the 
earth are formed of different materials, and, therefore, 
it is argued, their inhabitants differ in their intellectual 
capacities, the exaltation of intelligence rising in pro- 
portion to the * clearness and brightness' of the globe 
which they inhabit. Waiving the assumptions as to the 
materials of which the three bodies are composed and 
the habitation of them all* by intelligent beings, it is 
plain that there is no presumption in favour of the 
theory that the intelligence of the inhabitants stands in 
any relation to the material of the globe on which they 
live ; by parity of reasoning, birds ought to be far more 
intelligent than men. 

The following passage from Bacon's Novum Organum^ 
furnishes a remarkable example of an admixture of Con- 
fusion of Language with False Analogy : * Sed tem- 
poribus insequentibus, ex inundatione Barbarorum in 

•• Bk. I. Aph. Ixxvii. 



31 a FALLACIES INCIDENT 

imperium Romanum, postquam doctrina humana vck 
naufragium perpessa esset; turn demum philosophiac 
Aristotelis et Platonis, tanquam tabulae ex materia leviore 
et minus solida, per fluctus temporum servatse sunt' 
The student may exercise his sagacity in assigning its 
due share to each source of deception. 

The arguments for or against the independence of 
colonies will often be found to rest on a False Analogy. 
Sometimes it is said that, under no circumstances, ought 
a colony to rebel against the authority of the mother- 
country ; at other times, that, the colony having come to 
maturity, the time for its emancipation has arrived. In 
each of these cases the argument is suggested by the 
term 'mother-country/ Now the relations of the child 
to the parent are mainly determined by natural affection, 
by early associations, by gratitude for favours received, 
and frequently by the fact that, while the child is gra- 
dually approaching to the .prime of life, the parent 
is gradually receding from it. Similar circumstances 
though to a far weaker degree, may undoubtedly de- 
termine the relations of a colony to its ' mother-country,' 
as, for instance, sympathy of race, the associations of 
many of the colonists with their early home, gratitude 
for assistance received at the foundation of the colony 
or during the earlier years of its existence, the growing 
prosperity of the colony or the waning power of the 
* mother-country/ But, in addition to the fact that there 
are many cases in which these circumstances or some 
of them do not exist, or in which they exist only to 



TO INDUCTION. 313 

the slightest extent, it must be plain, on reflection, that 
the justice or injustice, the expediency or inexpediency, 
of separation from the mother-country or of repudia- 
tion by it must often be settled by considerations totally 
distinct from these, and such as receive no elucidation 
whatever from the relations between parent and child. 

The illusion, originating in a false analogy, that every 
conmiunity must, like every individual man, pass through 
the three stages of growth, vigour, and decay, is thus 
exposed by Sir G. C. Lewis®^ : 

* From what has been already said, it follows that the com- 
parison which is sometimes instituted between the progress 
of a community and the life of a man fails in essentials, and is 
therefore misleading. Both a man and a community, indeed, 
advance from small beginnings to a state of maturity ; but a 
man has an allotted term of life, and a culminating point from 
which he descends; whereas a community has no limited 
course to run ; it has no necessary period of decline and de- 
cay, similar to the old age of a man; its national existence 
does not necessarily cease within a certain time. Nations, as 
compared with other nations, have periods of prosperity and 
power ; but even these periods often ebb and flow, and when 
a civilised nation loses its pre-eminence — as Italy in the nine- 
teenth, as compared with Italy in the fourteenth and sixteenth 
centuries — it does not necessarily lose its civilisation. A po- 
litical community is renewed by the perpetual succession of 
its members ; new births, immigrations, and new adoptions of 
citizens, keep the political body in a state of continuous 
youth. No such process as this takes place in an individual 
man. If he loses a limb, it is not replaced by a fresh growth. 
The effects of disease are but partially repaired; all the 



67 



Methods of Observation and Reasoning in Politics, vol. ii. p. 438. 



314 FALLACIES ISCIDEST 

bodily and mental fimctions are gradnallT enfeebled, as fi» 
is prolongedy tiD at last decay ineritablj ends in death; 
whereas a commitnity might, consistently with the laws d 
hmnan nature, hare a duration co-eztensiTe with tliat d 
mankind* 

' The supposed analogy between the existence of a poG- 
tical community and the life of a man seems to hare con- 
tributed to the formation of the bdief in a liability to 
eorrvpt'um, inherent in erery society. It was a £iToarite 
doctrine among some writers of the last ce ntur y , tint every 
ctrilised community is filed to reach a period erf* c onmiUi M, 
when its healthy and natural action ceases^ and it undergoes 
some great deterioration. The notion of an inevitable stage 
of corruption in a nation was, indeed, partly suggested by the 
commonplaces condemnatory of luxury, derived both from 
the classical and ecclesiastical writers; and by the more 
modem eulogies of savage life. So £ir, however, as it was 
founded on the inevitable periods of decay in aniwiai and 
vegetable life, the comparison was delusive; for the two 
relations which are brought together do not corre^xMid. 
The death of individuals may, indeed, be considered a neces- 
sary condition for the progress of the society, into which they 
enter as temporary elements. It is by the substitution of 
new intelligences, and of natures not hardened to old customs, 
for minds whose thoughts and habits have learnt to move 
uniformly in the same groove, that progressive changes in 
human affairs are effected. The decay and death of the indi- 
vidual, therefore, tends not only to prevent the deterioration 
of the society, but to promote its improvement.* 

Ancient medicine was full of false analogies. We may 
take the following example from Dr. Paris'® : 

'An example of reasoning by false analogy is presented 

•• Pbarmacologiaf p. 64. 



TO INDUCTION, 315 

to us by Paracelsus, in his work de vita longd, wherein, 
speaking of antimony, he exclaims, " Sicut anlimonium finit 
aurum, sic, eadem ratione et forma, corpus humanimi purum 
reddit." ' 

The alchemists, or some of them, appear to have 
imagined that the same preparation by which they hoped 
to convert the baser metals into gold (called metaphori- 
cally 'the healthy man') would also be effective in re- 
moving the sources of all bodily diseases. Why should 
not the impurities of the human body be removable by 
the same means as the impurities of the metals ? 

* They [that is, the Arabian physicians] conceived,* says the 
same author ^^, * that gold was the metallic element in a state 
of perfect purity, and that all the other metals differed from 
it in proportion only to the extent of their individual con- 
tamination ; and hettce the origin of the epithet base^ as 
applied to such metals. This hypothesis explains the origin 
of alchemy; but in every history we are informed that the 
earlier alchemists expected, by the same means that they 
hoped to convert the baser metals into gold, to produce an 
universal remedy, calculated to prolong indefinitely the span 
of human existence. 

Ht is difficult to imagine what connexion could exist in 
their ideas between the ^^Philosopher's Stoncy* which was to 
transmute metals, and a remedy which could arrest the pro- 
gress of bodily infirmity : upon searching, however, into the 
writings of these times, it appears probable that this conceit 
may have originated with the alchemists from the applica- 
tion of false analogies, and that the error was subsequently 
diffused and exaggerated by a misconstruction of alchemical 
metaphors.' 

/ •• Pbarmacologia, p. 64. 



3l6 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

The old maxim that * Nature abhors a vacuum/ the 
once fashionable doctrine of the * Social Contract ' or 
* Original Compact/ the explanation of moral and phy- 
sical facts by applying to them the conceptions of * per- 
fect numbers* and * regular solids ^°/ the Pythagorean 
theory of the Harmony of the Spheres, the Aristotelian 
doctrine of the Mean, and innumerable other instances 
with which the student will meet in his reading, will 
abundantly illustrate the nature of False Analogy and 
its frequency in the reasoning of eariy speculators. 

The Argument from Final Causes'^, at least that 
extreme form of it which assumes that every natural 

'** On this subject the reader will find some very curious informatiou 
in Mill's Logic t Bk. V. ch. v. § 6, and WheweU's History of the Induc- 
tive Sciences^ 6k. IV. ch. iii. § a. 

"'^ * Turn vero, ad ulteriora tendens [intellectus humanus], ad proximiora 
recidit, videlicet ad causas finales, quae sunt plane ex natura hominis, 
potius quam universi : atque ex hoc fonte philosophiam miris modis 
corrupenint.* Bacon, Nov. Org, Lib. I. Aph. xlviii. To prevent mis- 
conception, I may state that I am far from denying that the Argument 
from Final Causes, if it take sufficient account of the evolution of or- 
ganisms and their power of adapting themselves to external circumstances, 
and if it be based on the contemplation of Nature as a whole, instead of 
on individual objects, may not admit of being stated in such a form as 
to occupy once more an important position in any scheme of Natural 
Theology. Moreover, even with respect to individual organisms, there 
are some cases of adaptation so marvellous, as that, for instance, of the 
eye, that it is difficult to exclude the idea of design, whatever may have 
been the agency, and however mysterious and prolonged the process, by 
which an intelligent Creator may have worked. The student will find 
a very temperate statement of the prevalent theory, together with much 
useful information on the literature of the subject, in Dr. Acland's 




TO INDUCTION. 317 

organism was specially designed to subserve some special 
object, and fashioned, once for all, in immediate reference 
to that object, appears ultimately to repose on a False 
Analogy. God or Nature (for both terms are used) is 
assimilated to a human artificer, and the argument ap- 
pears to rest on the assumption that the motives, con- 
ceptions, and contrivances of the one may be regarded 
as similar to those of the other. * Nature does nothing 
in vain/ * Nature always acts for the best/ * Everything 
is designed for some good purpose/ These and similar 
maxims express the general principle on which the 
argument rests. Of its application to special cases we 
may take the following examples. 

The instances given by Bacon, in the Advancement of 
Learning and the De Augmentis^^, when protesting against 

Harveian Oration for 1865. On the other side he may, with most 
advantage, consult the works of Mr. Herbert Spencer and Mr. Darwin. 

" Advancement of Learning, Bk. II. (Ellis and Spedding's edition, 
vol. iii. p. 358). Cf. De Augmentis, iii. 4. It should be noticed, how- 
ever, that Bacon allows the use of Final Causes in what he calls * Meta- 
physic/ Of the foregoing instances, * and the like,* he says that they 
are ' well enquired and collected in Metaphysic ; but in Physic they are 
impertinent.' And again : ' Not because these final causes are not true, 
and worthy to be enquired, being kept within their own province ; but 
because their excursions into the limits of physical causes hath bred a 
vastness and solitude in that track.* The rest of the paragraph may be 
read with advantage. What Bacon appears to mean (and the distinc- 
tion is important) is that we may argue, in Theology or Metaphysics, 
from an ascertained case of adaptation to the wisdom or goodness of the 
Creator, but that we are not justified in assuming adaptation or design 
as an instrument of physical investigation. Those who defend this use 
of the argument, would reply that many discoveries (such as, notably, 



3l8 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

the emplojonent of Final Causes in physical enquiiies, 
are the following : ' The hairs of the eye-Kds are for a 
quickset and fence about the sight ; the finnness of the 
skins and hides of living creatures is to defend than 
from the extremities of heat or cold ; the bones are for 
the columns or beams, whereupon the frames of the 
bodies of living creatures are built ; the leaves of trees 
are for protecting of the fruit ; the clouds are for water- 
ing of the earth; the solidness of the earth is for the 
station and mansion of living creatures.' 

The absurd extent to which the argument may be 
carried by speculators who attempt to find a Final 
Cause for every phenomenon which falls under their 
cognisance, will be plain from the examples which foUow. 
It would, however, be unjust to charge these absurdities 
to the account of those writers of the past generation 
who took a more sober, though, perhaps, an erroneous, 
view of the argument. 

In the TimcBus of Plato ''^ the construction of the whole 
universe, and specially of man, is explained on the 
principle of Final Causes. The following extract from 

Harvey's discovery of the circulation of the blood, which set out from 
observing the action of the valves in the veins of many parts of the body, 
and enquiring into their purpose) have been suggested by the idea of 
adaptation. See Acland's Harveian Oration^ and Dugald Stewart's Pbilo- 
sopby of the Human Mind, Part II. ch. xi. (Sir W. Hamilton's edition of 
Stewart's Works, vol. iii. p. 335, &c.) This may be, and, in fact, must 
be, admitted with respect to physiological enquiries (however the adapt- 
ation may be accounted for), and hence Bacon's prohibition is certainly 
too absolute. 

'' Of Plato, Bacon says truly, that he * ever anchoreth on that shore.' 



TO INDUCTION. 319 

Mr. Grote's Plato^^ will serve as a specimen of the 
method there employed : 

* The Demiurgus, having constructed the entire Kosmos, 
together with the generated Gods, as well as Necessity would 
permit — imposed upon these Gods the task of constructing 
Man : the second-best of the four varieties of animals whom 
he considered it necessary to include in the Kosmos. He 
furnished to them as a basis an immortal rational soul (di- 
luted remnant from the soul of the Kosmos); with which 
they were directed to combine two mortal souls and a body. 
They executed their task as well as the conditions of the pro- 
blem admitted. They were obliged to include in the mortal 
souls pleasure and pain, audacity and fear, anger, hope, ap- 
petite, sensation, &c., with all the concomitant mischiefs. By 
such uncongenial adjuncts the immortal rational soul was 
unavoidably defiled. The constructing Gods, however, took 
care to defile it as little as possible. They reserved the head 
as a separate abode for the immortal soul: planting the 
mortal soul apart from it in the trunk, and establishing the 
neck as an isthmus of separation between the two. Again 
the mortal soul was itself not single but double : including 
two divisions, a better and a worse. The Gods kept the two 
parts separate; placing the better portion in the thoracic 
cavity nearer to the head, and the worse portion lower down, 
in the abdominal cavity: the two being divided from each 
other by the diaphragm, built across the body as a wall of 
partition : just as in a dwelling-house, the apartments of the 
women are separated from those of the men. Above the 
diaphragm and near to the neck, was planted the energetic, 
courageous, contentious soul ; so placed as to receive orders 
easily from the head, and to aid the rational soul in keeping 
under constraint the mutinous soul of appetite, which was 

'* Vol. iii. pp. 273-75. 



3^0 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

planted below the diaphragm. The immortal soul was fas- 
tened or anchored in the brain, the two mortal souls in the 
line of the spinal marrow continuous with the brain : which 
line thus formed the thread of connection between the three. 
The heart was established as an outer fortress for the exer- 
cise of influence by the immortal soul over the other two. 
It was at the same time made the initial pomt of the veins, 
— the fountain from whence the current of blood proceeded 
to pass forcibly through the veins round to all parts of the 
body. The purpose of this arrangement is, that when the 
rational soul denounces some proceeding as "wrong (either 
on the part of others without, or in the appetitive soul 
within), it may stimulate an ebullition of anger in the heart, 
and may transmit from thence its exhortations and threats 
through the many small blood channels to all the sensitive 
parts of the body; which may thus be rendered obedient 
everywhere to the orders of our better nature. 

* In such ebullitions of anger, as well as in moments of 
imminent danger, the heart leaps violently, becoming over- 
heated and distended by excess of fire. The Gods foresaw 
this, and provided a safeguard against it by placing the lungs 
close at hand with the windpipe and trachea. The lungs 
were constructed soft and full of internal pores and cavities 
like a sponge ; without any bloody — but receiving, instead 
of blood, both the air inspired through the trachea, and the 
water swallowed to quench thirst. Being thus always cool, 
and soft like a cushion, the lungs received and deadened the 
violent beating and leaping of the heart ; at the same time 
that they cooled down its excessive heat, and rendered it 
a more equable minister for the orders of reason. 

* The third or lowest soul, of appetite and nutrition, was 
placed between the diaphragm and the navel. This region 
of the body was set apart like a manger for containing neces- 
sary food ; and the appetitive soul was tied up to it like a wild 
beast ; indispensable indeed for the continuance of the race 



TO INDUCTION. 321 

yet a troublesome adjunct, and therefore placed afar oiF, in 
order that its bellowings might disturb as little as possible 
the deliberations of the rational soul in the cranium for 
the good of the whole. The Gods knew that this appe- 
titive soul would never listen to reason, and that it must 
be kept under subjection altogether by the influence of 
phantoms and imagery. They provided an agency for this 
purpose in the liver, which they placed close upon the abode 
of the appetitive soul. They made the liver compact, smooth, 
and brilliant, like a mirror reflecting images: — moreover, 
both sweet and bitter on occasions. The thoughts of the 
rational soul were thus brought within view of the appetitive 
soul, in the form of phantoms or images exhibited on the 
mirror of the liver. When the rational soul is displeased, 
not only images corresponding to this feeling are impressed, 
but the bitter properties of the liver are all called forth. It 
becomes crumbled, discoloured, dark, and rough; the gall 
bladder is compressed ; the veins carrying the blood are 
blocked up, and pain as well as sickness arise. On the con- 
trary, when the rational soul is satisfied, so as to send forth 
mild and complacent inspirations, — all this bitterness of the 
liver is tranquillised, and all its native sweetness called forth. 
The whole structure becomes straight and smooth ; and the 
images impressed upon it are rendered propitious. It is 
thus through the liver, and by means of these images, that 
the rational soul maintains its ascendancy over the appetitive 
soul ; either to terrify and subdue, or to comfort and encou- 
rage it. 

* Moreover, the liver was made to serve another purpose. 
It was selected as the seat of the prophetic agency ; which 
the Gods considered to be indispensable, as a refuge and aid 
for the irrational department of man. Though this portion 
of the soul had no concern with sense or reason, they would 
not shut it out altogether from some glimpse of truth. The 
revelations of prophecy were accordingly signified on the liver, 



322 FALLACIES INCIDlEI^T 

for the instruction and within the easy vIcav of the appetitive 
soul ; and chiefly at periods when the functions of the rational 
soul are suspended — either during sleep, or disease, or fits of 
temporary extasy. For no man in his perfect senses comes 
under the influence of a genuine prophetic inspiration. Sense 
and intelligence are often required to interpret prophecies, 
and to determine what is meant by dreams or signs or prog- 
nostics of other kinds : but such revelations are received by 
men destitute of sense. To receive them, is the business of 
one class of men : to interpret them, that of another. It is a 
grave mistake, though often committed, to confound the two. 
It was in order to furnish prophecy to man, therefore, that 
the Gods devised both the structure and the place of the 
liver. During life, the prophetic indications are clearly 
marked upon it : but after death they become obscure and 
hard to decypher. 

*The spleen was placed near the liver, corresponding to 
it on the left side, in order to take off from it any impure or 
excessive accretions or accumulations, and thus to preserve it 
clean and pure.* 

Aristotle constantly employs this method of reasoning. 
Thus, in a familiar passage of the Ethics ''^ he szys 
that ' if it is better for men to attain happiness through 
their own exertions than through chance, it is reason- 
able to suppose that this will be the case, since every- 
thing that depends on Nature ^^ is in the best possible 
condition.' 

" Efb. Nic. i. 9 (5). Ei 8' kariv o0ra; ^iXriov ^ did n^^i/v c^9ai- 
fiovuv, iiXoyov ex^iv ovtojs, tiirtp rd kqt^ <f)vaiv, dts oT6v re iroAAi^ra 
I^X^^^t otfTO) iri<f>vK€v. 

""* The student will notice the transition from the Demiurgus and 
inferior gods of Plato to the 'Nature* of Aristotle. 'And in this,' says 



TO INDUCTION. 323 

From his physiological works (in which the argument 
is most commonly employed) it will be sufficient to ad- 
duce one or two examples, which will serve also to show 
how a preconceived opinion may lead an author to invent 
false facts for the purpose of supporting his theory. 

Having fixed the seat of sensation in the heart, in- 
asmuch as it is in the centre of the body, rather than 
in the brain, as some philosophers had done, it was 
necessary to discover some function for the brain. The 
necessity of discovering some function for it led to the 
fiction of its * coldness,' which was supposed to counteract 
the heat of the heart, and so to preserve the body 'in 
a mean state ^'^.^ On this account, he supposed, all 
animals which have blood are furnished with a brain, 
while bloodless animals, having little heat, require nothing 
to cool them, and are, therefore, without one. Moreover, 
in order to temper the coldness of the brain, blood is 

Bacon, * Aristotle is more to be blamed than Plato, seeing that he left 
out the fountain of final causes, namely God, and substituted Nature for 
God ; and took in final causes themselves rather as the lover of logic 
than of theology.* — The Dignity and Advancement of Learning (Trans- 
lation of \hcDe Augmentis), Bk. III. ch. iv. (Ellis and Spedding's Edition, 
vol. iv. p. 364). 

■" Compare the extraordinary fancy (in the same work, Bk. III. ch. iv.) 
that the reason why the heart, in man, inclines slightly towards the left 
side is that it may temper the greater coldness of that side {vpht rh 
Syiaovy t^ Kar&yfnj^iv rSav &piaT€pSt¥' iJu&Xiara yap twk AkXeay fyofl' 
Sy$panro$ Ix** KaTof/vyfxiva rd, dpiffT(pd). It is needless to observe 
that the left side of man is not colder than the right ; the fact is simply 
assumed in order to account for the position of the heart in a manner 
conformable to Aristotle's general theories. 

Y 2 



324 FALLACIES INCIDENT 

conveyed to the membrane which envelopes it by means 
of veins or channels. But, again, lest the heat so con- 
veyed should injure the brain, the veins, instead of being 
large and few, are small and many, and the blood con- 
veyed, instead of being copious and thick, is thin and 
pure^®. 

'The viscera are formed out of the blood, and therefore 
are only found in sanguineous animals, which necessarily have 
a heart; for it is clear that, having blood, which is a fluid, 
they must have a vessel to contain it, and hence also Nature 
has created veins ; and for these veins the origin must neces- 
sarily be one, since one, whenever possible, is better than 
many. The heart is the origin of the veins : this is seen in 
the fact that they spring from it, and do not go through it ; 
also they resemble it in structure. The heart has the chief 
position, namely, that of the centre, but more upwards than 
downwards, and rather in front than behind : for Nature is 
accustomed to seat the noblest in the noblest place, unless 
any stronger reason prevails : ot ftrj ri icwXvfi /nfifov^®.' 

The work of Bishop Wilkins, already quoted, furnishes 
some curious examples of the arguments which, even 
within the last two hundred years, have found favour with 
men distinguished for their scientific attainments*®. 

* But this [namely, a conceit of Philo's, in order to account 
for the spots in the moon, that * in the fabrick of the world, 

^® De Partibus Animalium^ ii. 7. Cf. Lewes* Aristotle^ § 164, p. 180. 

^* De Partibus Animalium, iii. 4. I here quote Mr. Lewes' summary, 
given in § 395, p. 310 of his Aristotle, 

^ Bishop Wilkins was one of the founders of the Royal Society, and 
enjoyed one of the highest scientific reputations of his time. 



TO INDUCTION. 325 

all things grow perfecter as they grow higher, and this is 
the reason why the moon doth not consist of any pure simple 
matter, but is mixed with air, which shows so darkly within 
her body'] cannot be a sufficient reason ; for though it were 
true, that nature did frame everything perfecter, as it was 
higher, yet is it as true, that nature frames everything fully 
perfect for that office to which she intends it. Now, had she 
intended the moon merely to reflect the sun-beams, and give 
light, the spots then had not so much argued her providence, 
as her unskilfulness and oversight, as if in the haste of her 
work, she could not tell how to make that body exactly fit 
for that office to which she intended it, 

' It is likely then, that she had some other end which 
moved her to produce this variety, and this in all probability 
was her intent to make it a fit body for habitation,, with the 
same conveniences of sea and land, as this inferior world doth 
partake of. For since the moon is such a vast, such a solid 
and opacous body, like our earth (as was above proved), why 
may it not be probable, that those thinner and thicker parts 
appearing in her do show the difference betwixt the sea and 
land in that other world ? and Galilaeus doubts not, but that 
if our earth were visible at the same distance, there would 
be the like appearance of it. 

' If we consider the moon as another habitable earth, then 
the appearances of it will be altogether exact, and beautiful, 
and may argue unto that, it is fully accomplished for all those 
ends to which Providence did appoint it. But consider it 
barely as a star or light, and then there will appear in it much 
imperfection and deformity, as being of an impure dark 
substance, and so unfit for the office of that nature ^^.* 

* Though there are some, who think mountains to be a de- 
formity to the earth, as if they were either beat up by the 
flood, or else cast up like so many heaps of rubbish left at the 

**- A Discovery of a New World in the Moon, pp. 66, 67. 



326 FALLACIES INtHDEXT 

Creation ; yet, if weU considered, they wfll be found as mud 
to conduce to the beauty and conTeniency of the universe, as 
any of the other parts. Nature (saith Pliny) purposdy fhmed 
them for many excellent uses : poirtly to tame the vicdaice of 
greater rivers, to strengthen certain joints within the vans 
and bowels of the earth, to break the force of the sea's iiran* 
dation, and for the safety of the earth's inhabitants^ vihether 
beasts or men®.' 

* I have now sufficiently proved that there are hills in the 
moon, and hence it may seem likely that there is also a worid- 
for since Providence hath some special end in all its worts 
certainly then these mountains were not produced in vain* 
and what more probable meaning can we conceive there 
should be, than to make that place convenient for habi- 
tation"?' 

* It hath been before confirmed, that there 'was a sphere of 
thick vaporous air encompassing the moon, as the first and 
second regions do this earth. 1 have now showed, that thence 
such exhalations may proceed as do produce the comets. 
Now from hence it may probably follow, that there may be 
wind also and rain, with such other meteors as are common 
amongst us. This consequence is so dependent, that Fro- 
mondus dares not deny it, though he would (as he confesses 
himself), for if the sun be able to exhale from them such 
fumes as may cause comets, why not such as may cause 
winds, why not then such also as may cause rain, since I have 
above showed that there is sea and land, as with us ? Now 
rain seems to be more especially requisite for them, since it 
may allay the heat and scorchings of the sun, when he is over 
their heads. And Nature hath thus provided for those in 
Peru, with the other inhabitants under the line®*.' 

^ A Discovery of a New World in the Moorit \>* *J*J. 
" Id. p. 91. ®* Id. p. lai 



TO INDUCTION. 327 

One of the most whimsical applications of the Argu- 
ment from Final Causes is to be found in the ' Doctrine 
of Signatures/ of which Dr. Paris thus speaks*' : — 

* But the most absurd and preposterous hypothesis that has 
disgraced the annals of medicine, and bestowed medicinal re- 
putation upon substances of no intrinsic worthy is that of the 
" Doctrine of Signatures," as it has been called, which is 
no less than a belief that every natural substance <ivbicb possesses 
any medicinal virtues^ indicateSy by an obvious and <well-marked 
external character, the disease for <wbicb it is a remedy , or the 
object for <wbicb it sbould be employed. This extraordinary 
monster of the fancy has been principally adopted and che- 
rished by Paracelsus, Baptista Porta, and CroUius, although 
traces of its existence may certainly be discovered in very 
ancient authors. 

* ♦ ♦ * * 

* The conceit, however, did not assume the importance of 
a theory until the end of the fourteenth century, at which 
period we find several authors engaged in the support of its 
truth, and it will not be unamusing to oiFer a specimen of 
their sophistry; they affirm that, since man is the lord of 
the creation, all other creatures are designed for his use, and 
therefore that their beneficial qualities and excellences must 
be expressed by such characters as can be seen and under- 
stood by every one ; and as man discovers his reason by 
speech, and brutes their sensations by various sounds, mo- 
tions, and gestures, so the vast variety and diversity of figures, 
colours, and consistencies, observable in inanimate creatures, 
is certainly designed for some wise purpose. It must be, 
in order to manifest those peculiar properties and excellen- 
ces, which could not be so effectually done in any other way, 
not even by speech, since no language is universal. Thus, 

** Pbarmacologia, pp. 47-50. 



328 FALLACIES INCIDRXT 

the lungs of a fox mtut be a specific for asthma, hecamse that 
animal is remarkable for its strong powers of respiratioiL 
Turmaick has a brilliant yellow colour, ^rhich indicates that 
it has the power of curing jaundice ; by the same rule, Pop^s 
must relieve diseases of the head ; • • . . and the Bupljraaa 
(eye-bright) acquired fame as an application in complaints of 
the eye, because it exhibits a black spot in its corolla resem- 
bling the pupil. In the curious work of Cbrysostom Magnem 
(Exercit. de Tabaco), we meet with a whimsical account of 
the signature of tobacco. "In the first place," says he, "the 
manner in which the flowers adhere to the head of the plant 
indicates the mfundibulum cerebri, and pitmtary gland ; in the 
next place, the three membranes, of which its leaves are com- 
posed, announce their value to the stomach, which has three 
membranes." 

* The blood-stone, the beliotropium of the ancients, from 
the occasional small specks or points of a blood-red colour 
exhibited on its green surface, is even at this day employed 
in many parts of England and Scotland to stop a bleeding 
from the nose ; and nettle-tea continues a popular remedy 
for urticaria. 

* * * * ^ 

* It is also asserted that some substances bear the signa- 
tures of the humours, as the petals of the red rose that of 
the blood, and the roots of rhubarb, and the flowers of 
saiFron, that of the bile. 

* I apprehend that John of Gaddesden, in the fourteenth 
century, celebrated by Chaucer, must have been directed by 
some remote analogy of this kind, when he ordered the son 
of Edward I., who was dangerously ill with the small-pox, 
to be wrapped in scarlet cloth, as well as all those who 
attended upon him, or came into his presence ; and even 
the bed and room in which he was laid were covered with 
the same drapery; and so completely did it answer sav 
the credulous historians of that day, that the prince was 



TO INDUCTION. 329 

cured without having so much as a single mark left upon 
him.* 

In these and similar instances, which might be multi- 
plied to almost any extent^®, it is plain that much is 
gained by the employment of the vague word Nature. 
Presuming that the majority of at least the more modern 
writers who have employed the Argument from Final 
Causes, if pressed to attach a definite meaning to the 
word, would reply that they regard it, in this connection, 
as only another name for God, the argument, as em- 
ployed in the above and similar examples (we are not 
here discussing the more refined employment of it), seems 
to rest on the three following assumptions : — 

(i) That God [or Nature] acts, not by laws, governing 
thie evolution of natural objects, but after the manner of 
a human artificer, having in view some special end in the 
production of each object and of each separate part of it. 

(2) That all objects are designed for the good of man, 
or, at least, of sentient or intelligent beings. 

(3) That we are so well acquainted with what is, on 
the whole, good for ourselves, or others, or the world 
at large, as well as with the general plan of the universe, 
that we are able, in each case, to pronounce positively 

^* The following example (taken from Plutarch, De Stoicorvm Repug- 
nantiis, p. 1042, by Mr. Lecky, in his History of European Morals, Jrom 
Augustus to Charlemagne, vol. ii. p. 174, note 2) is perhaps unsurpassed 
in absurdity : ' Chrysippus maintained that cock-fighting was the final 
cause of cocks, these birds being made by Providence in order to inspire 
lis by the example of their courage.' 



3^0 FALLACIES INCIDENT TO INDUCTION. 

on the ends which God [or Nature] proposed to himself 
in his constructions*^. 

Of these three assumptions, the first and second are, 
as we conceive, based on false analogies, the first trans- 
ferring to God [or Nature] the habit, observed in the 
human artificer, of producing each object with reference 
to some special end, and the second the motives which 
usually guide the artificer in the selection of those ends. 
The third assumption, it need hardly be added, involves 
a generalisation from a very narrow range of experience 
to operations co-extensive with all space and all time. 



Even though these various errors have been avoided, 
and the inductive process has been correctly performed, 
it is still possible, either through confusion of language, 
through mistaking the question at issue, or through 
drawing erroneous inferences in our subsequent deduc- 
tions, to arrive at false conclusions. But these are con- 
siderations which properly appertain to the other branch 
of Logic, which is concerned with deductive reasoning. 

^ The 'principle* laid down by Descartes {De Principiis Pbilosopbia, 
i. 28 ) supplies an appropriate commentary on this assumption : * Ita 
denique nullas unquam rationes circa res naturales, a fine, quern Deus 
aut natura in lis faciendis sibi proposuit, desumemus ; quia nou tantum 
nobis debemus arrogare, ut ejus consiliorum participes nos esse putemus.' 



INDEX. 



Adxquata causa, why the expres- 
sion is not here employed, 113. 

Adequate hypotheses, 99-103. 

Affirmative instances, tendency of 
the mind to notice, rather than 
negative instances, 238-243. 

Analogy, argument from, 209-220. 

— different meanings of the word, 

209, 210. - 

— fake, fallacy of, 304-330. 
Antiquitas saeculi juventus mundi, 

origin of the apophthegm, 
310. 

Antiquity, illegitimate use of the 
argument from, 308-316. 

Aristotle pointed out the depend- 
ence of deduction on induc- 
tion, 224. 

— his constant employment of 

inductio per simplicem enu- 
merationem, 262. 

— his constant employment of the 

argument from final causes, 

333. 
Authority, illegitimate use of the 

argument from, 268-274. 
Average of observations, 41. 

Bacon, his condemnation of induc- 
tio per simplicem enumera- 
tionem, 117, 261, 262. 



Bacon, his instantuB soUtari<Bt 134, 

135- 

— his instantia cruets ^ 142, 144. 

— his approximation to the in- 

ductive methods, 198-200. 

— his notice of the tendency to 

take account of affirmative 
rather than negative instances, 

238. 

— his criticism of the argument 

from final causes, 316-318. 
Bain, Professor, his view of the 

origin of universal beliefs, 28, 

29. 
Botany, reasons for the excellence 

of its classifications, 48. 

— nomenclature of, 82, 83. 

— terminology of, 85. 

Brown, Dr. Thomas, his view of 
the origin and nature of our 
conception of cause, 20. 

Causal relations, various kinds of, 
118-120. 

Cause, relation of, to the condi- 
tions of a phenomenon, 10- 
12. 

— nature of our conception of, 

15-24. 

— origin of our conception of, 

20, 21. 



33^ 



INDEX. 



Cause, definition of, 20. 

— error originating in mistaking 

a joint cause for a sole cause, 
281-290. 

— error originating in the con- 

fusion of the proximate with 
the primary or remote cause 
of a phenomenon, 294-797. 

— error due to neglecting to take 

into account the mutual ac- 
tion and reaction (mutuality) 
of cause and effect, 298-301. 

— error due to the inversion of 

cause and effect, 30 x -304. 
Causes, exciting, 12, 13. 

— predisposing, 12, 13. 

— final, illegitimate employment 

of the argument from, 316- 

330. 
Characteristick, 77, 78. 
Chemistry, nomenclature of, 84. 
<— method of difference extensively 

employed in, 144-145. 
Classification, 45-81. 

— scientific, distinguished from 

that employed in the aflfairs 
of ordinary life, 46-47. 

— scientific, regarded as subsidiary 

to induction, definition of, 47. 

— a natural system of, distin- 

guished from an artificial sys- 
tem of, 49, 50. 

— natural, rules for the right con- 

duct of, 65-73. 
Colligation of facts, a hypothesis 

serves for, 92. 
Conditions, relation of, to the 



cause of a phenomenon, lo- 
12. 

Consilience of inductions, 1 1 1, in. 
Continuity, law of, 75. 
Crucial instances, 1 42-1 44. 

Darwin, Mr., quoted on the signi- 
fication of the word * spedes,' 

74. 

Deduction, its relation to induc- 
tion, 224-230. 

Definition, are natural classes <k- 
termined by definition « 
type, 78-81. 

Descartes, his criticism of the argu- 
ment from final causes, 330. 

Diagnosis, 77, 78. 

Empirical generalisations or bwi 

208, 209. 
Exceptio probat regulam, the 

maxim explained, 284, 285. 
Exceptions to rules, 197. 
Experiment, 33-45. 

— distinguished from observation, 

33. 34- 

— general superiority of, over ob- 

servation, 35. 

— not open to us in the attempt 

to ascertain the cause of a 
given eflfect, 36, 37. 

— and observation, rules for the 

right conduct of, 39-45. 
Explanation, in the scientific sense, 
what, 91. 

Fallacies incident to induction, 
^37-330. 



INDEX. 



333 



Fallacies of generalisation, 259-550. 

— common to the employment of 

the various inductive methods, 
274.304. 

— the same instance may often 

be indifferently ascribed to 
several, 281. 
Fallacy of non-observation, 237- 

354- 

— of non-observation of instances, 

237-250- 

— of non-observation of circum- 

stances attendant on a given 
instance, 250-254. 

— of mai-observation, 254-259. 

— arising from treating the in- 

ductio per simplicem enu- 
merationem as if it were a 
valid induction, 260-274. 

— of * non causa pro causa,' 276- 

281. 

— due to the neglect of a joint 

cause, 281-290. 

— due to mistaking of joint effects 

for cause and effect, 290-294. 

— due to the confusion of the 

proximate with the primary 
or remote cause of a phe- 
nomenon, 294-297. 

— due to neglecting to take into 

account the mutual action 
and reaction (mutuality) of 
cause and effect, 298-301. 

— due to the inversion of cause 

and effect, 501-304. 

— of false analogy, 304-530. 

— due to the illegitimate emjdoy* 



ment of argument from £nal 
causes, 516-350. 
Final causes, fallacv due to the ille- 
gitimate emplo3niient of the 
argument from, 516-550. 

Geology abounds in instances of 
the employment of the method 
of concomitant variations, 185. 

Hamilton, Sir W., his criticism of 
Hume's theory on the nature 
of cause, 18, 19. 

Herschel, Sir John, distinctly recog- 
nises the inductive methods, 
197. 

— quoted on our tendency to 

notice affirmative rather than 
negative instances, 259, 240. 
Hume, his view of the nature of our 
conception of cause, 15-24. 

— injustice done to him by quoting 

from his treatise of Human 
Nature, 24. 
HjTpothesb, 89-115. 

— distinction between, and induc- 

tion, 8-10, 104-107. 

— description of, 90. 

— conditions of a legitimate^ 95- 

105. 

— difference between Mr. Mill and 

Dr. Whewell as to the func- 
tion of, 107-112. 

— gratuitous, 114, 115. 

Inductio per simplicem enumera- 
tionem, 116, 1 1 7, 205-209. 

— complete, 117. 



INDEX. 



335 



Method of concomitant variations, 

173-195- 

Methods, inductive or experi- 
mental, 116-204. 

Mill, James, quoted on the origin 
of our belief in the law of 
universal causation, 29. 

Mill, Mr., question between him 
and Dr. Whewell, as to whe- 
ther inductive inference be 
from the particular to the 
general, or from particulars 
to adjacent particulars, 13-15. 

— his view of the origin of uni- 

versal beliefs, 28, 29. 

— difference between him and 

Dr. Whewell as to the func- 
tion of hypotheses, 107-112. 

— importance now attached to 

the inductive methods mainly 
due to his influence, 197. 

Natural distinguished from artificial 
classification, 49, 50. 

— classification, rules for the right 

conduct of, 65-73. 

— groups, arrangement of, in a 

natural series, 70-73. 

— groups, constant recognition of 

new, 74-76. 
Newton, his demonstration of a 

central force, 105-108. 
Nomenclature, 81-84. 

Observarion, 33-45. 

— distinguished from experiment, 

33» 34- 



Observation, general emplojrment 
of, preceded that of experi- 
ment, 34. 

— alone open to us in the attempt 

to ascertain the cause of a 
given effect, 36, 37. 

— sciences wholly or mainly de- 

pendent on, at a great disad- 
vantage, as compared with 
those in which we can largely 
employ experiment, 37, 38. 

— and experiment, rules for the 

right conduct of, 39-45. 
Observations, importance of taking 
an average of, 41. 

Physiology frequently employs the 
method of concomitant varia- 
tions, 185, 186. 

Plato, his employment of the 
argument from final causes, 
318-322. 

Plurality of causes, 122-124. 

Power, question whether the idea 
of, is involved in our concep- 
tion of cause, 15-24. 

Prediction, value to be attached 
to, 108-1 1 1. 

Reid, his criticism of Hume's ac- 
count of causation, 18, 19. 

— his view of the nature of our 

conception of cause, 21. 

— his view of the origin of uni- 

versal beliefs, a6, 27. 

Social questions, the extreme dif- 
ficulty attendant on their in- 
vestigation, 267, 268. 



33^ 



JNDEX^ 



Species, practice of naturalists in 
stopping at, open to question, 

73, 74- 

Species and varieties, constant re- 
cognition of new, 74-76. 

Spencer, Herbert, his view of the 
origin of universal beliefs, 31, 
3a. 

Statistics, conclusions based on, are 
instances of the application of 
the method of concomitant 
variations, 194. 

Stewart, Dugald, his view of the 
nature of our conception of 
cause, a I. 

Subordination of characters, prin- 
ciple of, 67, 68. 

Terminology, 84-89. 
Type, persistency of, 76. 

— are natural classes determined 
by definition or, 78-81. 

Uniformity of nature, law of, 5, 6. 

— converse does not hold true, 6. 

— universality of the belief in, 24- 

26. 

— origin of the belief in, 26-32. 
Universal beliefs, various theories as 

to the origin of, 26-32. 



Universal causation, law of, 4, 5. 

— universality of the belief in, 24- 

a6. 

— origin of the belief in, 26-32. 

Variation of circumstances, im- 
portance of, 42, 43. 

Vera causa, why the expression is 
not here employed, 113, 114. 

Verification, 230-236. 

Whewell, Dr.. question between 
him and Mr. Mill as to whether 
inductive inference be from 
the particular to the general, 
or from particulars to adjacent 
particulars, 13-15. 

— his view of the origin of uni- 

versal beliefs. 27. 28. 

— his position that natural classes 

are determined not by defini- 
tion but by type. 78-81. 

— his remarks on terminology, 85- 

89. 

— difference between him and 

Mr. MiU as to the function 
of hypotheses, 107-112. 

— his criticism on the inductive 

methods, 201-204, 

Zoology, reasons for the excellence 
of its classifications. 48. 



October, 1871. 



BOOKS 



PRINTED AT 

THE CIiABEKBOK PBESS, OXFOBB, 

AND PUBUSHED FOR THE UNIVERSITY BY 

Tiff A fTMTTT. ATT AND CO., 

i6, BEDFORD STREET, COVENT GARDEN, LONDON. 



LEXICONS, OBAMMABS, Ao. 
A (Jreek-English Lexicon, by Henry George Liddell, 

D.D^ and Robert Scott. D.D. Sixth Edition^ Revised and Augmented, 1870. 
4to. cic€h, \L 16s-. 

A Qreek-Engllwh Lexicon, abridged from the above, 

chiefly for the use of Schools. Thirteenth Edition, 1869. square lama cieth, 
js. id, 

A copious Greek-English Vocabnlary, compiled from the 

best anthorities. 1850. 240110. bound, y. 

Oraeoae Grammaticae Bndimenta in usmn Scholarmn. 

Auctore Cardo Wordsworth, D.C.L. Seventeenth Edition, 187a xamo, bound, 4X. 

A Practical Introdnction to Greek Accentuation, by 

H. W. Chandler. M.A. 1863. 8ro. cieth, lor. 6d, 

ScbeUer's Lexicon of the Latin Tongue, with the German 

ezplanatioas translated into English by J. £. Riddle, M.A. 1835. foL cloth, 

l/. IX. 

A Practical Grammar of the Sanskrit Language, ar- 

rangfed with re f erence to the Classical Languages of Europe, for the use of 
En^ish Students, by Monier Winiams, M.A. Third Edition, 1M4. 8to. cloth, 
i5f. 

An Icelandic-English Dictionary. By the late R. Cleasby. 

Enlarged and completed by G. Vigfiissoo. Part I. 1869. 4ta x/. is. 

OBEEE Ain> LATTET CLASSICS. 
Aeschylus: Tragoediae et Fragmenta, ex recensione GuiL 

DindorfiL Second Edition, 1851. 8ro. cloth, y, 6d. 



Catalogue of Books 



Sophocles : Tragoediae et Fragmenta, ex recensione et cum 

conunentariis GulL DindorfiL Third hditwn^ a vols. z86o. fcan. 8to. ctcth, ' 

iL IS. ' 

Each Play separatdy, Umt^, ax. 6d. ' 

The Text alone, printed on writing paper, with laiEC 

mar^m, royal ifinoa cioth^ is. ^ 

The Text alone, square i6mo. cloib, 3s. 6J. 

Each Flay separately, lim^, 6d, 

Sophocles : Tragoediae et Fragmenta cum Annotatt. Gull. 

Dindorfii. Tomi II. 1849. Bra cloth, xos. 

The Text, VoL I. y. 6d. The Notes, VtA. II. 4r. 6d. 

Euripides : Tragoediae et Fragmenta, ex recensione Gull. 

DindorfiL Tomi II. 1834. 8vo. cloth, xos. 

Aristophanes: Comoediae et Fragmenta, ex recensione 

GuiL DindorfiL Tomi II. 1835. 8to. cloth, iix. 

Aristoteles; ex recensione Inmianuelis Bekkeri. Accedmit 

Indices Sylburgiani. Tomi XL 1837. 8va cloth, al. tos. 
Each volume separately, sr. 6d, 

Catulli Veronensis Ijiher. Reco^ovit, apparatum criticum 

prolegomena appendices addidit, Robinson EUis, A. M. 1867. 8vo. cloth, 16s. 

Demosthenes: ex recensione Guil. Dindorfii. Tomi IV. 

1846. 8vo. cloth. Price reduced /rom sL as. to i/. is. 

Homerus : Ilias, ex rec. Guil. Dindorfii. 1856. 8vo. clodf, 
Homerus: Odyssea, ex rec. Guil. Dindorfii. 1855. 8vo. 

cloth, y. 6d. 

Plato: The Apology, with a revised Text and English 

Notes, and a Digest of Platonic Idioms, by James RiddeU, M.A. X867 8vo. 
cloth, Ss.6d. 

Plato : Philehus, with a revised Text and English Notes, 

by Edward Poste. M.A. 1860. 8to. cloth, js. 6d. 

Plato : Sophistes and Politioiis, with a revised Text and 

English Notes, by L. Campbell, M.A. 1866. 8va cloth, xBs. 

Plato : Theaetetus, with a revised Text and English Notes, 

by L. Campbell, M.A. 1861. 8vo. cloth, 9s. 

Xenophon : Historia Graeca, ex recensione et cum annota- 

tio'nibus L. DindorfiL Second Edition, 1853. 8va cloth, xos. 6d. 

Xenophon : Expeditio Cyri, ex rec et cum annotatt. L. Din- 
dorfiL Second Edition, 1855. 8vo. cloth, los. 6d. 

Xenophon : Institutio Cyri, ex rec. et cum annotatt. L. Din- 
dorfii 1857. 8vo. cloth, los. 6d. 

Xenophon : Memorabilia Socratis, ex rec. et cum annotatt. 

L. DindorfiL 1862. 8va clothe js. 6d. 



Printed at the Clarendon Press, 



THE HOIiY SOBIFTUBES. 
The Holy Bible in the Earliest English Versions, made from 

the Latin Vulgate by John Wycliffe and his followers : edited by the Rev. J. 
Forshall and Sir F. Madden. 4 vols. 1850. royal 4to. cloth. Price reduced from 
5/. 15J. td. to 3/. 3^. 

The Holy Bible : an exact reprint, page for page, of the 

Authorized Version published in the year 1611. Demy 4to. kal^bound, it, is. 

Vetus Testajnentmn Gra.ece secundum exemplar Vaticanum 

Rotnae editum. Accedit potior varietas Codicis AlexandnnL Tomi III. 1848. 
iSmo. ctotA, i4t. ' 

Novum Testamentiun Gra>ece. Edidit Carolus Lloyd, 

S.T.P.R., necnon Episcopus Oxoniensis. 1869. i8mo. ctotA, y. 

The same on writing paper, small 4to. clotb^ los. 6d. 
Novum Testajnentum Graece juxta Exemplar Millianum. 

1868. i8mo. ctoth, 2S. 6d. 

The same on writing paper, small j^to.xlotb, 6s. 6d, 
Evangelia Sacra Graeoe. 1870. fcap. 8vo. limp, is. 6d. 

EOCLESIASTIOAIi HISTOBY, &o. 
Baedae Historia Ecclesiastioa. Edited, with English 

Notes, bv George H. Moberly, M.A., Fellow of C. C. C, Oxford. 1869. crown 
8vo. ctotn, 10s. 6a. 

Bingham's Antiquities of the Christian Church, and other 

Works. 10 vols. 1855. 8vo. ctotA, Price reduced front 5/. sj. to 3/. 3^. 

Burnet's History of the Beformation of the Church of 

England. A new Edition. Carefully revised, and the Records collated with 
the originals, by N. Pocock, M.A. With a Preface by the Editor. 7 vols. 1865. 
8vo. cloth^ 4/. 4r. 

Eusebii Famphili Historia Ecclesiastica. Svo. cloth, Ss. 6d. 
Fatrum Apostoliconun, S. Clementis Romani, S. !^atii, 

S. Polycarpi. quae supersunt. Edidit Guil. Jacobson, S.T.P.R. Tomi II. 
Fourth Edition, 1863. 8vo. ctoth, it. is. 

ENGLISH THEOLOGY. 
Butler's "Works, with an Index to the Analogy. 2 vols. 

1849. 8vo. ctoth, lis. 

GresweU's Harmonia Evangelica. Fi/tb Edition, 1856. 

8vo. cloth, 9s. 6d. 

Hooker's "Works, with his Life by Walton, arranged by 

John Keble, M.A. Ftyth Edition, 1865. 3 vols. 8vo. cloth, it. iis. 6d. 

Hooker's Works ; the text as arranged by John Keble, M.A, 

2 vols. 1865. 8vo. cloth, lis. 

Pearson's Exposition of the Creed. Revised and corrected 

by E. Burton, D.D. Fifth Edition, 1864. 8va cloth, los. 6d. 

Waterland's Review of the Doctrine of the Eucharist, with 

a Preface by the present Bishop of London. z868. crown 8vo. cloth, 6s. 6d. 



I 




RcwenTm Hkcorr of A^padtix tad 'Prices az F^ g?.*^-? >n 



avitft. 



I An JLeeooBt of Viwiiiim, br Jofex fkil^s. BfJL, F ILSL, 
Tfimim on TiiilnitiMJaMi GUoiIbk. Bt BBrthokMnev 

\'JL IIL Seaen. 

MISCELIiAHSOUB. 
A Coarse of I«eetiires on Art* delhnered before the UniveT^ 




tk.y 'A fytifir± By John Rosiua. M.A^ Sbde Pto fcaa w of Fine Aft. id^ 

»r'„ eUik, t$. ' 

A Critical Aooonnt of Ae Drawings by Michel Angelo 

•M Kaiaeflo in the Uairersity GoOeries. OxionL Bj J. C Robmso^^S^A. 

Bacon's Novum Organum, edited, with English Xotes. br 

G. W. Kitchin. M. A 1855. Sra cMA. 9r. 6^ "^ 

Bacon's Novum Organimi, translated by G. W. Kitdiin, 
Smith's Wealth of B'ations. A new Edition, with Notes* 

by J, E. Thorold Rogers. M. A 2 rob. Stol cMA. zu. . 

Gail Institationnm Juris Cirilis Commentarii Qoatnor ; ! 

or, ii\cmtnt% of Roman Law by Gains. With a Translatioa and Coaunentary. ' 
Ky lidward Potte. M. A.. Banriscer-at*Law. aad Fdknr of Oriel College. Oxfotd. 
Kvo. cMA, lit, yutt/ublitfud. 



€ilanniirffn l^xm ^ttin. 



The Delegates of the Clarendon Press having undertaken 
the publication of a series of works, chiefly educational, and 
entitled the Clarentlon ^ress Serks* have published, or have 
in preparation, the following. 

Those to which prices are attached are already published; the others are in 

preparation. 

I. GBEEK AND LATIN OIiASSIOS, &o. 
A Greek Primer, in English, for the use of beginners. By 

the Right Rev. Charles Wordsworth, D.C.L., Bishop of St. Andrews. Second 
. Edition. Ext. fcap. 8vo. cloth, is. id. 

Greek Verbs, Irregular and Defective; their forms, 

meaning, and quantity ; embracing all the Tenses used by Greek writers, with 
reference to the passages in which they are found. By W. Veitch. New 
Edition. Crown 8vo. cloth, zos. 6d. yust publisheeL 

The Elements of Greek Aooentuation (for Schools) : 

abridged from his larger work by H. W. Chandler, M.A., Waynflete Professor 
of Moral and Metaphysical Philosophy, Oxford. Ext fcap. 8vo. cloth, ss. 6d. 

Aesohines in Otesiphontem and Demosthenes de Oorona. 

With Introduction and Notes. By G. A. Simcox, M.A., and W. H. Suncox, 
M.A,, Fellows of Queen's College, Oxford. In the Press. 

Aristotle's Folitios. By W. L. Newman, M.A., Fellow 

and Lecturer of Balliol College, and Reader in Ancient History, Oxford. 

The Golden Treasury of Ancient Greek Poetry ; being a 

Collection of the finest passages in the Greek Classic Poets, with Introductory 
Notices and Notes. By R. S. Wright, M.A., Fellow of Oriel College, Oxford. 
Ext. fcap. Svo. cloth, Zs. 6d. 

A Golden Treasury of Greek Prose ; being a Collection of 

the finest passages in the principal Greek Prose Writers, with Introductory 
Notices and Notes. By R. S. Wnght, M.A., Fellow of Oriel College, Oxford ; 
and J. E. I> Shadwell, M.A., Senior Student of Christ Church. Ext. fcap. Svo. 
cloth, 4s. 6d. 

Homer. Iliad. By D. B. Monro, MA., Fellow and Tutor 

of Oriel College, Oxford. 

Homer. Odyssey, Books I-XII (for Schools). By W. W. 

Merry, M. A., Fellow and Lecturer of Lincoln College, Oxford. Ext. fcap. Svo. 
cloth, 4s. 6d. 



Clarendon Press Series. 



Homer. Odyssey, Books I-XII. By W. W. Merry, M.A^ 

Fellow and Lecturer of Lincoln CoUesfe, Osforcf : and the late lames Riddell 
M.A.. FeUow of Balliol CoUege. Oxford. ■' ^^' 

Homer. Odyssey, Books XIII-XXIV. By Robinson Ellis, 

M. A., Fellow of Trinity CoUq^e, Oxford. 



Plato. Selections (for Schools). With Notes, by B. Towett, 

M.A., Keeius Professor of '^ — *- ■ — * * **■ »* « — ~ - _ 

of Balliol College, Oxford. 



M.A., Regius Professor of Greek ; and J. Punres. M. A., Fdlow and Lectnrer 



Sopliooles. Oedipus Rex: DindorTs Text, "with Notes by 

the Ven. Archdeacon Basil Jones, M.A., formerly FeUow of University Colleen 
Oxford. Second Edition. £xt, fc^. 8vo. limp cloth, is. 6d. 

Sophocles. By Lewis Campbell, M.A., Professor of Greek, 

St. Andrews, formerly Fellow of Queen's CoOege, Oxford. /» tA^ Press 

Theocritns (for Schools). With Notes, by H. Snow, MA. 

Assistant Master at Eton College, formerly Fellow of Sl John's CoU^e. Cam- 
bridge. Ext. fcap. 8va cloth, 4s. 6d. ^ 

Xenophon. Selections (for Schools). With Notes and 

Maps, by J. S. Phillpotts, B.C.L., Assistant Master in Rufby SchooL forniM^v 
Fellow of New CoUege, Oxford. Ext. fcap. 8vo. cloth, y. 6d. i""»eny 

Caesar. The Commentaries (for Schools). Part I. The 

Gallic War, with Notes and Maps, &c, by Charles E. Moberly, M. A.. Assistant 
Master in Rutfby School ; formerly Scholar of Balliol College, Oxford. Ext 
fcap. 8vo. cloth, 4s. 6d. 

Also, to follow : Part IL The Civil War : by the same Editor. 

Cicero's Fhilippio Orations. With Notes, by J. R. Kin^, 

M.A., formerly Fellow and Tutor of Merton College, Oxford. Demy 8%^ 
cloth, 10s. 6d. 

Cicero pro Cluentio. With Introduction and Notes. By 

W. Ramsav, M.A. Edited by G. G. Ramsay, M.A., Professor of Humanity 
Glasgow. Ext. fcap. 8vo. cloth, y. td. '* 

Cioero. Selection of interesting and descriptive passages. 

With Notes. By Henry Walford, M.A., Wadham College, Oxford, Assistant 
Master at Haileybury College. In three Parts. Ext fcafi. 8vo. clothe 4s. 6d. 

Also sold separately. 
Part L Anecdotes from Grecian and Roman History, cloth, xs. 6dl 
Part II. Omens and Dreams : Beauties of Nature, cloth, is. 6d. 
Part III. Rome's Rule of her Provinces, cloth, is. 6d. 

Cioero. Select Letters. By Albert Watson, M.A., Fellow 

and Tutor of Brasenose College, Oxford. Demy 8vo. cloth, i8r. 

Cicero de Oratope. With Introduction and Notes. By 

A. S. Wilkins, M. A., Professor of Latin, Owens Collie, Manchester. 



Clarendon Press Series. 



Cicero and PUny. Select Epistles (for Schools). With 

Notes bvE. R. Bernard, M.A.. Fellow of Maedalen College. Oxford, and 
the late C. E. Prichard, M.A., formerly Fellow of Balllol College, Oxford. /» 
tMg Press. 

ComeUus Nepos. With Notes, by Oscar Browning, M.A., 

Fellow of King's College, Cambridge, and Assistant Master at Eton CoU^e. 
Ext. fcap. 8va cMh, as. id. 

Horace. With Notes and Introduction. By Edward C. 

Wickham, M.A., Fellow and Tutor of New College, Oxford. 
Also a small edition for Schools. 

Iiivy, Books I-X. By J. R. Seeley, M.A., Fellow of Christ's 

College, and Regius Professor of Modem History, Cambridge. Book I. Demy 
8vo. clotk^ 6s. Ncfw ready. 

Also a small edition for Schools. 

Ovid. Selections for the use of Schools. With Introduc- 
tions and Notes, and an Appendix on the Roman Calendar. By W. Ramsay, 
M.A. Edited by G. G. Ramsay, M. A., Professor of Hnmanity, Glasgow. Ext. 
fcap. 8va cloth, y. 6d. 

Fragrments and Specimens of Early Latin. With Intro- 
duction, Notes, and Illustrations. By John Wordsworth, M.A., Brasenose 
College, Oxford. 

Selections from the less known Iiatin Poets. By North 

Finder, M.A., formerly Fellow of Trinity College, Oxford. Demy 8vo. cloth. 

Passages for Translation into Latin. For the use of 

Passmen and others. Selected by J. Y. Sai^cnt, M.A., Tutor, formerly Fellow, 
of Magdalen College, Oxford. Second Edition. Ext fcap. Sra cloth, ar. 6d. 



II. MENTAL AND MOBAL PHILOSOPHY. 
The Elements of Deductive Logic, designed mainly for 

the use of Junior Students in the Universities. By T. Fowler, M.A., Fellow 
and Tutor of Lincoln College, Oxford. Fourth Edition, with a Collection of 
Examples. Ext. fcap. 8vo. cloth, y. 6d. 

The Elements of IndiLCtive Logic, designed mainly for 

the use of Students in the Universities. By the same Author. Ext. fcap. 8vo. 
cloth, 6s. 

A Manual of Political Economy, for the use of Schools. 

By J. E, Thorold Rogers. M.A., formeriy Professor of Political Economy, 
Oxford. Second Edition. Ext. fcap. Sva doth, ^r. 6d 

III. MATHEMATICS, Ac. 

Acoustics. By W. F. Donkin, M.A., F.R.S., Savilian Pro- 
fessor of Astronomy, Oxford. Crown 8va cloth, js. 6d. 



8 Clarendon Pras 



An EleiDontftry Treatise on Queini nioim By P. G. 

Tait. M.A.. PnrfesBor of Nttnril Fhaosophy m idle Uni » enily of E Jia b i gh; 
focmerlyFdlowarSC.Peta'sColkgci.CaabndKie. Deaqr 8vo. c^M, izr. 6^ 

Book-keeping- By R. G. C. Hamilton, Acconntant to the 



Board of Trade, and joha Ball (of tlie Fim of Messrs. Qoilter. ifan, & CoJ. 
Examiners m Book-kecpii^ for the Socae^ of Arts' iK^^««i«-»yM»n i. TTtird 
Edition. Ext. fcapL 8to. lim^ cloth, is. 6d. 

A Ck>nr8e of laectnres on Fore Oeometry. By Henry J. 

Stephen Smith. M. A., F.R.S.. Fdknr of Baffiol CoQege. and SaWBan Ptafessor 
of Geometiy in the Unirersity of Oxford. 

A Treatiae on Slectrioity and MagnetJanu By J. Clerk 

Maxwell. M. A., F.R.S.. foraetly IVoicssor of Natural Flaiosoi^y, Kbit's Col- 
lege, London. In the Press. 

A Series of Elementary Works it being arranged, anti ■Wfill shortly be 

nfiftfHftcpd. 

TV. HI8TOBY. 
A Manual of Ancient History. By Geoi^ Rawlinson, 

M. A . Camden ProfesstM- of Ancient History, formerly FeOow of Exeter CoQeee, 
Oxford. Demy Bra cloth, i\s. 

Select Charters and other Illnstrations of liSTigiiaTi 

Constitutional History from the Earliest "Hmes to the nan of Edward L 
By W. Stubbs, M.A.. Regius Professor oi Modem History m the University 
of Oxford. Crown 8vo. cloth, 8r. 6d, 

A Constitutional History of Tlngland. By W. Stubbs, 

M. A, Kq^us Professor of Modem History in the University of Oxford. 

A History of Germany and of the Empire, down to the 

close of the Middle Ages. By J. Brirce, B.CL., Fellow of Oriel CoDeee. 
Oxford. 

A History of Germany, from the Reformation. By Adol- 

Ehus W. Ward, M.A., Fellow cX St. Peter's Cdl^e, Cambridge, Ptofessor of 
[istory, Owens College. Manchester. 

A History of British India. By S.J. Owen, M.A.. Lee's 

Reader in Law and History, Christ 
History in the University ot Oxfmrd. 



Reader in Law and History, Christ Church, and Teacher of Indian Law and 
"' - ofC " ■ 



A History of Greece. By E. A. Freeman, MA., formerly 

Fellow of Trinity College, Oxford. 

A History of France. By G. W. Kitchin, M.A., formerly ' 

Censor of Christ Church. 

Elements of Law for the use of Students. By William ■ 

Markby. M.A., one of the Justices of the High Court of Judicature, Calcutta. ' 
Nearly ready. I 

Commentaries on Boman Law ; from the original and the 

best modem sources. V^y H. J. Roby, M.A., formeriy Fellow of St. John's 
College, Cambridge ; Professor of Law at University College, London. 



Clarendon Press Series. 



VI. FHTSICAIi SCrBNCE. 

Natural Fhilosopliy. In four volumes. By Sir W. Thom- 
son, L.L.D., D.C.L., F.R.S., Professor of Natural Philosophy, Glasgow; and 
P. G. Tah, M.A., Professor of Natural Philosophy, Edinburgh; formerly Fel- 
lows of St. Peter's College, Cambridge. VoL 1. 8va cloth, u. $s. 

By the same Authors, a smaller Work on the same subject, 

forming a complete Introduction to it, so far as it can be carried out with 
Elementary Geometry and Algebra. In the Press. 

Descriptive Astronomy. A Handbook for the General 

Reader, and also for practical Observatory work. With 234 illustrations and 
numerous tables. By G. F. Chambers, F.R.A.S., Barrister-at-Law. DemySvo. 
856 pp., cloth, i/. IS. 

Chemistry for Students. By A. W. Williamson, Phil. 

Doc.. F.R.S., lYofessor of Chemistry, University College, London. A new 
Edition., ivith ^littions. Ext fcap. 8vo. cloth, &r. (xL 

A Treatise on Heat, with numerous Woodcuts and Dia- 
grams. By Balfour Stewart, LL.D., F.R-S., Director of the Observatory at 
Kew. Second Edition. Ext. fcap. 8to. cloth, js. 6d. yust published. 

Forms of Animal Idfe. By G. RoUeston. M.D., F.R.S., 

Linacre Professor of Physiology, Oxford. Illustrated by Descriptions and 
Drawings of Dissections. Demy Sva cloth, idr. 

Exercises in Practical Chemistry. By A. G. Vernon 

Harcourt, M.A., F.R.S., Senior Student of Christ Church, and Lee's Reader 
in Chemistry ; and H. G. Madan, M. A., Fellow of Queen's College, Oxford. 

Series I. Qualitative Exercises. Crown 8va cloth, 7X. td. 
Series II. Quantitative Exercises. ^ 

The Valley of the Thames : its Physical Geography and 

Geology. By John Pliillips, M.A., F.R.S., Professor of Geology, Oxford. 
In the Press. 

Geology. By J. Phillips, M.A., F.R.S., Professor of Geo- 
logy, Oxford. 

Mechanics. By Bartholomew Price, M.A., F.R.S., Sedleian 

Professor of Natural Philosophy, Oxford. 

Optics. By R. B. Clifton, M.A., F.R.S., Professor of Experi- 
mental Philosophy, Oxford ; formerly Fellow of St. John's College, Cambridge. 

Electricity. By W. Esson, M.A., F.R.S., Fellow and 

Mathematical Lecturer of Merton College, Oxford. 

Crystallography. By M. H. N. Story-Maskel3aie, M.A., 

Professor of Mineralogy, Oxford ; and Deputy Keeper in the Department of 
Minerals, British Museum. 

Mineralogy. By the same Author. 



Physiological Physios. By G. Griffith, M A., Jesus Col- 
lege, Oxford, Assistant Secretary to the British Association, and Natural 
Science Master at Harrow School 

Magnetism. 

VII. ENGIiISH IiANaXTAGE AND IiITSBATTTBE. 
A First Beading Book. By Marie Eidiens of Berlin ; and 

edited by Anne J. Clough. Ext fcap. 8vo. stiff corvers, 4^> 

Oxford Beading Book, Part I. For Little Children. 

Ext. fcap. 8vo. stiff covers, td. 

Oxford Beading Book, Pait II. For Junior Classes. 

ExL fcap. 8vo. stiff covers, 6e[. 

On the Principles of Grammar. By E. Thring, MA., 

Head Master of Uppingham School Ext fcap. 8to. ciotA, 4s. 6d. 

Grammatical Analysis, designed to serve as an Exercise 

atid Composition Book in the English Language. By E. Thring^, M. A., Head 
Master of Uppingham School Ext fcap. Svo. cloth, y. 6d. 

Specimens of Early English ; being a Series of Extracts 

from the most important English Authors. Chronologicall]^ arranged, illustrative 
of the progress of the English Languskge and its Dialectic varieties, from A.D. 
1250 to A.D. 140a With Grammatical Introduction, Notes, and Glossary. By 
R. Morris, Editor of " The Story of Genesis and Exodus." &c. Ext fcap. 8va 
doth, js. 6d. 

Specimens of English from a.d. 1394 to a.d. 1579 (from 

the Crede to Spenser) : selected by W. W. Skeat, M.A., formerly Fellow of 
Christ's College, Cambridge. In tfu Press. 

The Vision of "William concerning Piers the Plowman, 

by William Langland. Edited, with Notes, by W. W. Skeat, M.A., formerly 
Fellow of Christ^ College, Cambridge. Ext. fcap. Svo. cioth, 4^ . 60. 

The Philology of the English Tongue. By J. Earle, 

M.A., formerly Fellow of Oriel College, and Professor of Anglo-Saxon, Oxford. 
Ext. fcap. Svo. cloth, 6s. 6d. ynst published. 

Tsrpical Selections from the best English Authors from the 

Sixteenth to the Nineteenth Century, (to serve as a higher Reading Book,) with 
Introductory Notices and Notes, being a Contribution towards a History of 
English Literature. Ext. fcap. Svo. cloth, 4J-. td. 

Specimens of the Scottish Language; being a Series of 

Annotated Extracts illustrative of the Literature and Philology of the Lovdand 
Tongue from the Fourteenth to the Nineteenth Century. With Introduction 
and Glossary. By A. H. Burgess, M.A. 

See also XII, below for other English Classics. 

VIII. FKENOH IiANGTTAaE AND IiITEBATUBB. 
Brachet's Historical Granmiar of the French Language. 

Translated by G. W. Kitchin, M.A., formerly Censor of Christ Church. ExL 
fcap. Svo. cloth, 3s. 6d. 



Clarendon Press Series, 1 1 



An Etymological Dictionary of the French Language, with 

a Preface on the Principles of French Etymology. By A. Brachet. Iranslated 
by G. W. Kitchin, M.A., formerly Censor of Christ Cliwch. In the Press, 

Comeille's Cinna, and Molidre's Les Femmes Savantes. 

Edited, with Introduction and Notes, by Gustave Masson. . Ext fcap. 8vo. 
cloth, 2S. 6d. 

Bacine's Andromaque, and Comeille's Le Menteur. With 

Louis Racine's Life of his Father. By the same Editor. Ext fcap. 8vo. doth, 

Molidre's Les Fourberies de Scapin, and Bacine's Athalie. 

With Voltaire's Life of Moli&re. By the same Editor. Ext fcap. 8vo. cloth, 
as. 6d. 

Selections from the Correspondence of Madame de S6vign6 

and her chief Contemporaries. Intended more especially for Girls' Schools. 
By the same Editor. Ext fcap. 8vo. c/oth, 3s. 

Voyage autour de ma Chambre, by Xavier de Maistre; 

Ourika. by MADAME DE DURAS; La Dot de Suzette, by FlEVEE ; Les Ju- 
meaux de I'H&tel Comeille, by Edmond ABOUT ; M€saventures d'un £coher, 
by RODOLPHE ToPFFER. By the same Editor. Ext fcap. 8vo. cloth, 2s. bd. 

A French Grammar. A Complete Theory of the French 

Language, with the rules in Freuch and Ene^lish, and numerous Examples to 
serve as first Exercises in the Language. Bv Jules Bu^, Honorary M.A. of 
Oxford ; Taylorian Teacher of French, Oxfora : iixaminer in the Oxford Local 
Examinations from 1858. 

A French. Grammar Test. A Book of Exercises on French 

Grammar: each Exercise being preceded by Grammatical Questions. By the 
same Author. 

Exercises in Translation No. i, from French into English, 

with general rules on Translation ; and containing Notes, Hints, and Cautions, 
founded on a comparison of the Grammar £md Genius of the two Languages. 
By the same Author. 

Exercises in Translation No. 2, from English into French, 

on the same plan as the preceding book. By the same Author. 

IX. GEBMAN' liANGTJAGE AND IiITEBATUBE. 
Goethe's Egmont. With a Life of Goethe, &c. By Dr. 

Buchheim, Professor of the German Language and Literature in King's Col- 
lege. London ; and Examiner in German to the University of London. Extra 
fcap. 8vo. cloth, y. 

Schiller's Wilhelm Tell. With a Life of Schiller ; an histo- 
rical and critical Introduction. Arguments, and a complete Commentary. By 
the same Editor. Ext fcap. 8vo. cloth, y. 6d. 

Iiessing's Minna von Bamhelm. A Comedy. With a Life 

of Lessing, Critical Commentary, &c. By the same Editor. 



Clarendon Press Series. 



X. ABT, &<]. 



A Handbook of Fiatorkl Art. By R. St. J. Tyrwhitt. 
A Treatiae on Harmony. By Sir F. A. Gore Ouseley, 

A Troatiaa on Counterpomt, Canon, and Fugue, based 

XI. MI8CrBIjI.ANEOirS. { 

The Modem Oreek LanEuage in its relation to Ancient 

The CultlTation of the Bpeaking Voice. By John HuUah. 



XII. A 8EBIES as XNOI.IBH OLASBIOS. 

Dej'igmd to meet the 'wanti of StudenU in Englitb Lile- 
raturt: under the juperintendence of the Rev. J. S. 
Brewer, M.A., of Queen' College, Oxfird, and Prefesjor 
of Eighth IJterature at Kin^i College, London, 

he (tudcnt of English Lite. 
le ontset of bis lailc ; — hit reading it apt to 
be too narrow or too diffuie. 

Out or tlie van number of authors Kt before him in boolu 
professing to deal -with this iubject he kno".i not which to idect ; 
he thinks he must read a little of all; hcsonn ahiudontto hope- 
less an attempt ; he endi by comcniin^ hinuFlfwith second-hand 
information i and professing 10 -iiudy English Literature, he fait* 
to master a single English auihor. On the other hand, by con- 



Clarendon Press Series. 13 

fining his attention to one or two writers, or to one special period 
of English Literature, the student narrows his view of it ; he fails 
to grasp the subject as a whole ; and in so doing misses one of 
the chief objects of his studjr. 

How may these errors be avoided ? How may minute reading 
be combined with comprehensiveness of view ? 

In the hope of famishing an answer to these questions the 
Delegates of the Press, acting upon the advice and experience of 
Professor Brewer, have determined to issue a series of small 
volumes, which shall embrace, in a convenient form and at a 
low price, the general extent of English Literature, as repre- 
sented in its masterpieces at successive epochs. It is thought 
that the student, by confining himself, in the first instance, to 
those authors who are most worthy of his attention, will be 
saved from the dangers of hasty and indiscriminate reading. By 
adopting the course thus marked out for him, he will become 
familiar with the productions of the greatest minds in English 
Literature ; and should he never be able to pursue the subject 
beyond the limits here prescribed, he will have laid the founda- 
tion of accurate habits of thought and judgment, which cannot 
fail of being serviceable to him hereafter. 

The authors and works selected are such as will best serve to 
illustrate English Literature in its historical aspect. As * the eye 
of history,' without which history cannot be understood, the 
literature of a nation is the clearest and most intelligible record 
of its life. Its thoughts and its emotions, its graver and its less 
serious modes, its progress, or its degeneracy, are told by its best 
authors in their best words. This view of the subject will sug- 
gest the safest rules for the study of it. 

With one exception all writers before the Reformation are 
excluded from the Series. However great may be the value of 



14 Clarendon Press Series. 



literature before that epoch, it is not completely nationid. For 
it had no common organ of language; it addressed itself to 
special classes ; it dealt mainly with special subjects. Again ; of 
writers who flourished after the Reformation, who were pcxHilar 
in their day, and reflected the manners and sentiments of their 
age, the larger part by far must be excluded from our list. 
Common sense tells us that if young persons, who have bat a 
limited time at their disposal, read Marlowe or Greene, Burton, 
Hakewill or Du Bartas, Shakespeare, Bacon, and Milton will be 
comparatively neglected. 

Keeping, then, to the best authors in each epoch and here 

popular estimation is a safe guide — the student will find the fol- 
lowing list of writers amply sufllicient for his purpose : Chaucer 
Spenser, Hooker, Shakespeare, Bacon, Milton, Dryden, Bunyan, 
Pope, Johnson, Burke, and Cowper. In other words, Chaucer is 
the exponent of the Middle Ages in England ; Spenser of the 
Reformation and the Tudors; Hooker of the latter years of 
Elizabeth ; Shakespeare and Bacon of the transition from Tudor 
to Stuart ; Milton of Charles I and the Commonwealth ; Dryden 
and Bunyan of the Restoration ; Pope of Anne and the House 
of Hanover ; Johnson, Burke, and Cowper of the reign of 
George HI to the close of the last century. 

The list could be easily enlarged; the names of Jeremy 
Taylor, Clarendon, Hobbes, Locke, Swift, Addison, Goldsmith 
and others are omitted. But in so wide a field, the difficulty is 
to keep the series from becoming unwieldy, without diminishinf 
its comprehensiveness. Hereafter, should the plan prove to be 
useful, some of the masterpieces of the authors just mentioned 
may be added to the list. 

The task of selection is not yet finished. For purposes of 
education, it would neither be possible, nor, if possible, desirable 
to place in the hands of students the whole of the works of the 



Clarendon Press Series. 15 

authors we have chosen. We must set before them only the 
masterpieces of literature, and their studies must be directed, not 
only to the greatest minds, but to their choicest productions. 
These are to be read again and again, separately and in combina- 
tion. Their purport, form, language, bearing on the times, must 
be minutely studied, till the student begins to recognise the full 
value of each work both in itself and in its relations to those that 
go before and those that follow it. 

It is especially hoped that this Series may prove useful to 
Ladies- Schools and Middle Class Schools ; in which English 
Literature must always be a leading subject of instruction. 



A General Introduction to the Series. By Professor 

Brewer, M.A. 

1. Chaucer. The Prologue to the Canterbury Tales ; The 

Knightes Tale ; The Nonne Prest his Tale. Edited by R. Morris, Editor for 
the liarly English Text Society, &c., &c. Second Edition. Extra fcap. 8vo. 
cloth, 2^. 6d. 

2. Spenser's Faery Queene. Books I and II. Designed 

chiefly for the use of Schools. With Introduction. Notes, and Glossary. By 
G. w. Kitchin, M.A., formerly Censor of Christ Church. Extra fcap. 8vo. 
ciotA, as. 6d. each. 

3. Hooker. Ecclesiastical Polity, Book I. Edited by R. W. 

Church, M.A,, Rector of Whatley ; formerly Fellow of Oriel College, Oxford. 
Extra fcap. 8vo. ctoth, as. 

4. Shakespeare. Select Plays. Edited by W. G. Clark, 

M.A., Fellow of Trinity College, Cambridge; and W. Aldis Wright, M.A., 
Trinity College, Cambridge. 

I. The Merchant of Venice. Extra fcap. 8vo. stiffcwtrs, is. 

II. Richard the Second. Extra fcap. 8vo. stiff covers^ is. 6d. 

III. Macbeth. Extra fcap. 8vo. stiff covers, xs. 6d. 

5. Bacon. Advancement of Learning. Edited by W. Aldis 

Wright, M.A. Extra fcap. 8vo. cUtA, 4s. 6d. 

6. Milton. Poems. Edited by R. C. Browne, M.A., and 

Associate of King's College, London, a vols. Ext fcap. 8vo. ciotA, dr. 6d. 
Sold separately, WoL I. \s.,Vo\. II. y. 



1 6 Clarendon Press Series. 



7. Dryden. Stanzas on the Death of Oliver Cromwell; 

Astraea Redux : Annus MirabOis ; Absalom and Achitophel ; Relifio Laid ; 
The Hind and the Panther. Edited by W. D. Christie. M. A.. Trinity College. 
Cambridsre. Extra fcap. 8vo. cMh, y. 6d, 

I 8. Bunyan. Grace Abounding; The Pilgrim's Progress. 

Edited by E. Venables, M.A., Canon of Lincoln. 



I 



9. Pope. With Introduction and Notes. By Mark Pattison, 

B.D., Rector of Lincoln College, Oxford. 

I. Essay on Man. Extra fcap. Sra stiff covers^ is. 6el, 
II. Epistles and Satires. In tJte Press. 

10. Johnson. Rasselas; Lives of Pope and Dryden. Edited 

by C. H. O. Daniel, M. A., Fellow and Tutor of Worcester College, Oxford. 

11. Burke. Thoughts on the Present Discontents ; the Two 

Speeches on America ; Reflections on the French Revolution. By Mark Patti- 
son, B.D., Rector of Lincoln College, Oxford. 

12. Cowper. The Task, and some of his minor Poems. 

Edited by J. C. Shairp, M. A., Principal of the United CoUege, St. Andrews. 



Published for the ITniversity by 
MACMIIiLAN AJTD GO., IiOmDOIT. 



The Delegates op the Press invite suggestions and advice 
from all persons interested in education; and will he thankful 
for bints, &c., addressed to either the Rev. G. W. KrrcHDf, 
St, Gileses Road East, Oxford, or the Secretary to the 
Delegates, Clarendon Press, Oxford. 



f^ 



I